Tag Archive for: Dios

Bart Ehrman is a professor of religious studies at UNC-Chapel Hill in North Carolina. He is well known for his best-selling books critiquing core tenets of evangelical Christianity and, in particular, the reliability of New Testament sources. Regular readers of my articles will already know that Ehrman is not the most careful scholar when it comes to his use of ancient sources. A few days ago, Ehrman posted two blog entries ( here and here ) on his website, claiming that the idea that Jesus is himself Yahweh is a recent doctrinal innovation, completely foreign to the New Testament and the early church. Ehrman even goes so far as to say that this is the view of only “some conservative evangelical Christians” and that “I have never even heard the claim (let alone a discussion of it) until very recently.” Furthermore, Ehrman adds,

I, frankly, had never heard of such a thing until six years ago. Maybe I wasn’t listening in Sunday school, or maybe I was sleeping through those particular lectures at Moody Bible Institute; or maybe… Nah, I don’t think so. If anyone knows otherwise, please let me know. But I can’t think of any ancient Christian source that speaks of Jesus as Yahweh himself. Jesus is the son of Yahweh.

Ehrman claims that,

The first time I heard someone say with authority that Jesus was Yahweh and that this was standard Christian teaching was in a debate I had with Justin Bass in 2015 – you can listen to it on Youtube. I don’t remember at what point in the debate he said it, but he made some comment about Jesus being Yahweh, and I froze. I thought: theologians have never called Jesus Yahweh!

That a scholar of Ehrman’s stature would be misinformed about orthodox Christian teaching on such a fundamental issue is absolutely astonishing. In this article, I respond to Ehrman’s articles and show that he is profoundly mistaken about the teaching of the New Testament and the early church.

The first Christian theologians

Ehrman wonders “if there are early Christian theologians who hold this view.” Yes, there are many. For example, Justin Martyr (~100-165), in his dialogue with Trypho the Jew, wrote [1] ,

…now you will permit me first to relate the prophecies, which I wish to do to prove that Christ is called both God and Lord of hosts…

I don’t know how one can be clearer than that. Irenaeus (~130-202) also states [2] ,

For I have shown from the Scriptures that none of the sons of Adam is called God or Lord in all things and absolutely. But that He Himself is in His own right, beyond all men who have ever lived, God, and Lord, and Eternal King, and the Incarnate Word, proclaimed by all the prophets, the apostles, and by the Spirit Himself, can be seen by all who have attained even a small portion of the truth.

Ignatius of Antioch (~50-108) also affirmed the full deity of Christ. For example, in his epistle to the Ephesians, he wrote [3] ,

We also have as our Physician the Lord our God, Jesus the Christ, the only begotten Son and Word, before time, but who later also became man, from the virgin Mary.

I could go on quoting the early church fathers for quite a while, but this should suffice to show that the view that Jesus is Yahweh, the eternal God, is not a new idea but goes back to the early church. I will now turn to Ehrman’s comments on the New Testament.

Is the name Yahweh found in the New Testament?

Ehrman states that

Of course, the name Yahweh is not found in the NT at all, as it is a Hebrew word, and the NT is written in Greek. The NT does not give God a personal name.

This is obviously true since the New Testament was written in Greek, not Hebrew. However, the New Testament uses an equivalent word – in fact, the word that replaces the Hebrew tetragrammaton YHWH in the Septuagint Greek translation of the Hebrew Bible. This word is κύριος, which is translated “Lord” in our English Bibles. It is of course true that this word had a broader range of meaning than simply denoting Yahweh (for example, Paul uses it of earthly masters – see Eph 6:5). However, the meaning of the Greek words, as intended by the original author, can be teased out by an examination of the context. For example, Hebrews 1:10-12 quotes Psalm 102:25-27:

“You, Lord, laid the foundations of the earth in the beginning, and the heavens are the work of your hands. 11 They will perish, but you will remain. They will all wear out like a garment. 12 You will roll them up like a cloak, and they will be changed like a robe. But you are the same, and your years will have no end.”

Verse 10 uses the word κύριος, which is evidently (given the fact that the author is quoting an Old Testament Psalm concerning the Lord God) intended to denote Yahweh. What makes this text especially noteworthy for our purposes here is that the author of Hebrews applies the words of this Psalm to Jesus. In fact, this Hebrew scripture is one of several applied to Jesus in Hebrews 1, as the author compares and contrasts the exaltation of the Son with that of angelic beings.

To take another example, consider Paul’s quotation of Joel 2:32 in Romans 10:13: “For ‘everyone who calls on the name of the Lord will be saved.'” Again, this alludes to an Old Testament text that refers to Yahweh. But Paul introduces this text only a few verses after having declared that “if you confess with your mouth that Jesus is Lord and believe in your heart that God raised him from the dead, you will be saved” (Rom. 10:9). The implication here is that the κύριος of verse 9 is the same referent as in verse 13 – namely, Jesus. In other words, Jesus is the Yahweh of Joel 2:32, on whose name we are to call. This point is made even more explicitly by Paul in 1 Corinthians 1:2: “To the church of God which is in Corinth, to those sanctified in Christ Jesus, called to be saints, together with all those who in every place call on the name of our Lord Jesus Christ, both their Lord and ours.” This text again clearly alludes to Joel 2:32, except that the Lord (κύριος) whom we are to call upon is none other than Jesus Christ.

Another example is found in 1 Peter 2:2-4:

“2 As newborn babes, long for the pure milk of the word, that by it you may grow up in your salvation, 3 if indeed you have tasted that the Lord is good. 4 As you come to him, you are a living stone rejected by men but chosen and precious in God’s sight…”

Verse 3 quotes Psalm 34:8 (“Oh, taste and see that the LORD [Yahweh] is good!”). However, verse 4 identifies the κύριος of Psalm 34:8 as none other than Jesus himself (the closest antecedent of the pronoun “he” in verse 4 is “the Lord” of verse 3). This implies that Jesus is the Yahweh of Psalm 34:8.

Another example is found in 1 Peter 3:14-15

“14 But even though you may suffer for righteousness’ sake, you will be blessed. Do not be afraid of them, nor be troubled, 15 but in your hearts honor Christ the Lord as holy…”

It is true that there is some level of ambiguity about the original reading of verse 15, as most later manuscripts read θεόν (“God”) rather than Χριστόν (“Christ”). However, Bruce Metzger points out that [4] ,

The reading Χριστόν , however, is strongly supported by early and diversified external evidence… as well as by transcriptional probability, the more familiar expression ( κύριον τὸν θεόν ) substituting the less usual expression ( κύριον τὸν Χριστόν ). The omission of τὸν Χριστόν in the patristic treatise Promissionibus attributed to Quodvultdeus must be due to an accidental oversight of the translator or copyist.

If (as seems likely) the original reading is indeed “Christ the Lord,” then we have another example of an Old Testament text referring to Yahweh applied to Jesus. Compare 1 Peter 3:14-15, above, with Isaiah 8:12-13:

12 “Do not call all that this people call conspiracy a conspiracy, and do not fear what they fear, nor be afraid. 13 But you shall honor the LORD of hosts as a holy one.”

Isaiah 8:12 is quoted by 1 Peter 3:14. Isaiah 8:13 is quoted by 1 Peter 3:15, except that instead of calling his readers to honor the Lord of hosts as holy (as Isaiah did), Peter implores his readers to honor Christ the Lord as holy. Thus we have another case in which the title κύριος (which is correctly interpreted here as a substitute for the Hebrew tetragrammaton) is applied to Jesus.

I could continue along a similar line for a considerable time. However, I trust that this is enough to dispel Ehrman’s argument that the New Testament does not use the name Yahweh and therefore never calls Jesus Yahweh.

Does Psalm 110 rule out Jesus being Yahweh?

Ehrman continues,

When Christians wanted to find another divine being in the Old Testament to identify as Christ, they turned to passages like Psalm 110: “The LORD said to my Lord, ‘Sit at my right hand until I make your enemies your footstool.'” Based on what I said in my previous post, you can reconstruct who is speaking to whom here (note that the first LORD is capitalized and the second is not): “YHWH said to Adonai….”

Ehrman’s entire argument here implicitly presupposes Unitarianism. If the doctrine of the Trinity is true, then there is no problem with the persons within Yahweh’s being or essence being distinguished from one another and even participating in conversation with one another. Nor is there any problem with the Father exalting the Son, since the Son had willingly humbled himself through his incarnation and death on the cross. No Trinitarian identifies the Son with the Father. Rather, the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are each distinctive persons who together share fully in Yahweh’s essence, each possessing the divine attributes fully and completely.

Ehrman’s rendering of the words used in Psalm 110:1 is not entirely accurate, as it does not say “YHWH said to Adonai…” but rather “YHWH said to Adoni.” This difference may seem trivial (especially since these two words are distinguished only by a difference in Masoretic vowel pointing), but it is actually important. The title “Adonai” is used exclusively as a divine title (essentially as a synonym for YHWH). In fact, the ancient Hebrews, rather than pronouncing the divine name, would say “Adonai.” The word “Adoni,” by contrast, is simply the possessive form of the Hebrew word “Adon,” meaning “Lord” or “Master” (the Hebrew equivalent of the Greek word κύριος). The word can be used to refer to Yahweh, depending on the context, but it is not reserved exclusively to Yahweh. The upshot of this is that, although many Christians have used this text to argue for a plurality of divine persons (and, indeed, for the deity of Christ), the reality is that any such argument based on this text is going to require more work and nuance than it often receives. I don’t think this text is as conclusive as the previous texts we’ve looked at. However, it is, I would argue, certainly suggestive, as we’ll see. The context sheds some light on the referent of verse 1. In verse 5-7 of Psalm 110, we read,

The Lord is at his right hand; he will crush kings on the day of his wrath. He will judge the nations, heaping up the dead and crushing the rulers of the whole earth. He will drink from a brook along the way, and so he will lift up his head on high.

In the Hebrew, verse 5 identifies the one sitting at Yahweh’s right hand as none other than Adonai, a word only used to refer to deity. Thus, Psalm 110 implies a plurality of divine persons within the Godhead. One possible response to this is that Psalm 110:5 is simply the inversion of Psalm 110:1. Just as David’s Lord sits at Yahweh’s right hand, so too Yahweh is at the right hand of David’s Lord. For example, in Psalm 109:31, Yahweh is at the right hand of the needy, and in Psalm 16:8, Yahweh is at the right hand of the psalmist David. The problem with this argument is that if one continues reading Psalm 110, it is clear that the “He”s in verses 5-7 all refer to Adonai, and in verse 7 this individual is said to drink from a stream, a human function. Thus, the individual sitting at the right hand of Yahweh in Psalm 110 appears to be a divine-human person.

Furthermore, Jesus himself argues that “David himself calls him ‘Lord.’ How then can he be his son?” (Mark 12:37). What Jesus means is that none of David’s descendants could be greater than he. Therefore, he cannot refer to an ordinary human descendant of David. The question then arises as to what kind of Lord he could be referring to. But we can go even further. David’s Lord cannot be any human king either, since in Psalm 2:10-12 all kings must be subject to David, and Psalm 89:26-27 tells us that,

“I will appoint him [David] as my firstborn, the greatest of the kings of the earth”

Nor can He be a mere angelic creature, since angels serve God’s elect and are themselves servants (cf. Heb. 1:7, 14; Rev. 19:10 and 22:8-9). Who is left then? God.

The Angel of the Lord

Ehrman notes that Christians (such as Justin Martyr in the second century) have often identified the angel of Yahweh in the Hebrew Bible as a pre-incarnate manifestation of Christ. He writes,

I wonder if the confusion among some evangelicals about the Christian understanding of Christ (when they say He is Yahweh) is because the “Angel” of the LORD is so fully representative of YHWH Himself that He is sometimes called YHWH after He is clearly identified NOT as YHWH but as His angel. Why would He be called YHWH if He were YHWH’s messenger? It would be something like if a messenger from the king comes to you and orders you to do something, you tell your neighbors that the “king” told you to do something. Well, actually, His messenger did it, but he was so fully representative of the king that his words were the king’s words.

This interpretation, however, does not account for the fact that several people throughout the Hebrew Bible marvel at the fact that they have seen the angel of Yahweh and yet their lives are spared (people are not supposed to be able to see Yahweh and live – Exodus 33:20). For example, consider Jacob’s words after he wrestles with a man in Genesis 32, one who is identified in Hosea 12:4 as the angel of Yahweh: “Then Jacob called the name of the place Peniel, saying, ‘For I have seen God face to face, and yet my life has been spared.'” Further support that the individual Jacob wrestled with was the angel of Yahweh comes from the parallelism between Genesis 32:29 and Judges 13:18, in which the man and the angel of Yahweh respectively say, upon being asked for their name, “Why do you ask my name?”

Another instance of this is in Judges 6, where we read of Gideon’s encounter with the angel of Yahweh. In verses 22-24, we read,

22 Then Gideon perceived that it was the angel of the LORD. And Gideon said, “Alas, LORD God! For now I have seen the angel of the LORD face to face.” 23 But the LORD said to him, “Peace be with you. Do not be afraid; you will not die.” 24 So Gideon built an altar there to the LORD and called it, “The LORD is Peace.” To this day it stands in Ophrah, which belongs to the Abiezrites.

Another example is found in Judges 13, which records the appearance of the angel of Yahweh to Manoah and his wife to announce the birth of Samson. In verse 21-22, we read,

21 The angel of the Lord no longer appeared to Manoah and his wife. Then Manoah knew that it was the angel of the Lord. 22 And Manoah said to his wife, “We are sure to die, because we have seen God . “

Thus, we see that numerous texts (and there are many I have not mentioned) attest to the deity of the angel of Yahweh. While Ehrman is correct in pointing out that many of these texts also distinguish the angel of Yahweh from God, this is quite consistent with a Trinitarian paradigm that sees God’s messenger as Yahweh and yet in another sense distinct from Yahweh.

Ehrman’s interpretation of the angel of the Lord passages also fails to explain the parallelism seen in Genesis 48:15-16, in which we read of Jacob’s blessing of Joseph’s sons. He said,

15 “The God before whom my fathers Abraham and Isaac walked, the God who has been my shepherd all my life long until this day, 16 the angel who has redeemed me from all evil, may he bless the boys…”

Here we see a poetic parallel in which the angel is identified with God. In fact, in the Hebrew, verse 16b uses the singular pronoun “let him bless the lads,” implying that the angel and God are one and the same.

I discuss the topic of the angel of the Lord in much more detail here and here .

The Carmen Christi

Ehrman then turns his attention to Christ’s poem in Philippians 2:5-11. He writes,

When Christ is exalted after his death, God gives him “the name that is above every name” for all creation to worship and confess. This is a reference to Isaiah 45 where Yahweh alone has the name above every name for all to worship and confess only him.

Possibly these modern Christians are thinking that Christ must therefore have been given the name YHWH, and therefore he *is* YHWH. But the passage does not seem to mean that. The supreme LORD of all, YHWH, is the one who *gives* Jesus the name that is above all others. It is worth noting that in this very passage, when God gives Jesus his “name,” it does not mean that he has made a name change for Jesus. On the contrary, the passage says that the name before which all will bow in worship and confession is *Jesus*! (not YHWH): “That at the name of Jesus every knee should bow and every tongue confess.” Jesus’ own name is exalted.

However, this is not the argument at all. I do not interpret the “name” in verse 9 to be a personal name. Rather, in my view, this is best understood as a reference to Christ’s reputation that he received as a consequence of his humiliation and death on the cross.

There are at least three mutually supporting arguments for the deity of Christ that can be adduced from this text. First, this text is primarily concerned with Christ’s humility, for “though he was in the form of God, he did not consider equality with God something to be grasped” (Phil. 2:6). This only makes sense if Christ is equal in status to God, for humility is not praised for not exalting oneself to a higher status than one is entitled to. If I refrain from overthrowing the monarchy and exalting myself as king, I should not be praised for my humility in restraining myself. The text is therefore best understood if Christ voluntarily stripped himself of the divine privilege that was rightfully his. This reading is also supported by the Greek. In fact, the construction is known as a double object-complement accusative. Daniel Wallace explains that [5] ,

A double accusative object complement is a construction in which one accusative is the direct object of the verb and the other accusative (whether noun, adjective, participle, or infinitive) complements the object in the sense that it predicates something about it.

In this case, the verb is οὐχ ἡγήσατο (“did not count”), the direct object is τὸ εἶναι ἴσα θεῷ (“equality with God”), and the object complement is ἁρπαγμὸν (“a thing to be grasped”). Thus, the relationship between the direct object and the object complement is rather like an equality sign. In other words, Jesus did not consider equality with God to be a thing to be grasped (ἁρπαγμὸν). Furthermore, Roy Hoover has argued that it is actually an idiomatic expression, “referring to something already present and at one’s disposal.” The question… [is] whether or not one decides to exploit something” [6] Hoover observes that in all cases where this noun ἁρπαγμός is the complement of the object in a construction like this (where the verb is to consider or to see or to regard), it always means something like an exploitable advantage. Therefore, Hoover argues, one could reasonably translate this text to be saying that Christ did not regard equality with God as something to be taken advantage of .

A second consideration is that Paul uses the Greek word μορφῇ in verse 6 to describe Christ as having the form of God and uses this same word in verse 7 to describe Christ as taking the form of a servant. This implies that Christ was in the form of God in the same sense that He took upon Himself the form of a servant. Since Christ was literally a servant, “being born in the likeness of men” (v. 7b), it follows that Christ was also literally God.

Third, Ehrman rightly points out that verses 10-11 allude to Isaiah 45:23, in which we read, “To me [i.e., Yahweh] every knee will bow, every tongue will swear allegiance.” However, in the context of Philippians 2:10-11, every knee bows and every tongue swears allegiance to Jesus. Indeed, that is what it means to confess that Jesus Christ is Lord (κύριος), which literally means master.

Conclusion

To conclude, contrary to Ehrman’s claims, the view that Jesus is Yahweh has been the orthodox Christian position for nearly two millennia, and is taught in the New Testament. Ehrman claims that the name Yahweh is never used in the New Testament and that therefore the New Testament authors could not have applied it to Jesus. However, the New Testament does use the equivalent Greek term κύριος. Although this word is also used to describe earthly masters, the word is often used to denote Yahweh when the New Testament quotes the Old Testament, and often these texts are explicitly applied to the person of Jesus. Ehrman’s argument from the New Testament’s use of Psalm 110 presupposes a unitary paradigm. Although Ehrman argues that the angel of the Lord in the Hebrew Bible is only Yahweh’s agent who is invested with divine authority, this argument collapses on the basis of the various exclamations of surprise following an encounter with the angel of the Lord that one has survived despite having seen God face to face. Finally, Ehrman is mistaken regarding Philippians 2:5-11, which is best read as indicating that Christ willingly laid aside the divine privilege that was rightfully His to take the form of a servant.

Footnotes

[1] Justin Martyr, “Dialogue with Tryphon,” in The Apostolic Fathers with Justin Martyr and Irenaeus, ed. Alexander Roberts, James Donalds. Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and A. Cleveland Coxe, vol. 1, The Ante-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Company, 1885), 212.

[2] Irenaeus of Lyons, “Irenaeus Against Heresies,” in The Apostolic Fathers with Justin Martyr and Irenaeus, ed., Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson, and A. Cleveland Coxe. Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and A. Cleveland Coxe, vol. 1, The Ante-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Company, 1885), 449.

[3] Ignatius of Antioch, “Letter of Ignatius of Antioch to the Ephesians,” in The Apostolic Fathers with Justin Martyr and Irenaeus, ed. Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and A. Cleveland Coxe, vol. 1, The Ante-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Company, 1885), 449. Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson, and A. Cleveland Coxe, vol. 1, The Ante-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Company, 1885), 52-200.

[4] Bruce Manning Metzger, United Bible Societies, A Textual Commentary on the Greek New Testament, Second Edition a Companion Volume to the United Bible Societies Greek New Testament (4th Rev. Ed.) (London; New York: United Bible Societies, 1994), 621-622.

[5] Daniel B. Wallace, Greek Grammar Beyond the Basics: An Exegetical Syntax of the New Testament (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1996), 182.

[6] Roy W. Hoover, “The Harpagmos Enigma,” Harvard Theological Review 64 (1971).

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek  

 

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

Dr. Jonathan McLatchie is a Christian writer, international speaker, and debater. He holds a BS (Hons) in Forensic Biology, an M.Res in Evolutionary Biology, a second MS in Medical and Molecular Biosciences, and a PhD in Evolutionary Biology. He is currently an Adjunct Professor of Biology at Sattler College in Boston, Massachusetts. Dr. McLatchie contributes to several apologetics websites and is the founder of the Apologetics Academy (Apologetics-Academy.org), a ministry that seeks to equip and train Christians to persuasively defend the faith through regular webinars, as well as to assist Christians struggling with doubt. Dr. McLatchie has participated in over thirty moderated debates around the world with representatives of atheism, Islam, and other alternative worldview perspectives. He has lectured internationally in Europe, North America and South Africa promoting an intelligent, thoughtful and evidence-based Christian faith.

Original Blog: https://cutt.ly/dWH1oIA

Translated by Yatniel Vega Garcia

Edited by Elenita Romero

 

By Mia Langford

The “omnis” of theology – omnipresence, omniscience, omnipotence, etc. – are coming under attack with increasing frequency, and not only from the more well-known theologically liberal camps of Christianity. Examples abound – even within evangelical communities – of these attacks on various attributes of God, which seem to have been “shot down” by the fire of academics, or are altered by laymen to the point that the essence of the word is lost, and along with it, the force that would inspire in the individual worship and wonder.

What is causing the traditional understanding of God to “fade away”? It seems as if  the nail holding all these attributes in place has been removed.

In this week’s episode of Why Do You Believe?, Dr. Richard Howe gives that nail a name: classical theism.

Classical Theism

Classical theism is a theology about God that denotes His simplicity. The word classical must be understood within the boundaries and categories of Western thought that emerged with the ancient Greeks, followed by the Christian church fathers, and then the medieval scholastics.

Within this framework, God is uninterrupted or infinitely present, invariable existence, not a being composed of metaphysical parts like the rest of creation (for example, angels are composed of form and existence, human beings have a mixture of form, matter and existence, etc.).

All of God’s attributes, such as omnis, immutability, and others, are derived from this metaphysical principle of simplicity (the quality of the attribute describes a characteristic of God’s nature or of His actions, and both can be known through creation [general revelation] and through His Word [special revelation]). God’s attributes   are not independent, but are in such harmony that they are all involved and collaborate at all times and moments; by eliminating or altering one attribute, the others simply collapse.

Put another way, representing God’s attributes individually has to do with our finite, human understanding attempting to segment God’s magnitude and majesty into pieces that are easier to perceive, and when we misuse the cornerstone of divine simplicity, or any other essential attribute of God, the whole house falls into jeopardy.

Who removed the nail?

So, if simplicity is the foundation of many of God’s attributes, why has simplicity been neglected in modern times? Dr. Howe attributes this omission primarily to a lack of skill in hermeneutics . And he demonstrates in these few lines that an insufficient and erroneous view of the nature and attributes of God will result in the omission of this precious and firm theological principle, and will end in an absurd and incorrect interpretation of the text. In classical theism, God is honored as unique in his kind because he is a necessary and simple being, but other philosophical systems are capable of imposing human, finite, and inexact characteristics on God very often.

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek  

 

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

Original Blog: https://cutt.ly/sQJ8OJP

Translated by Yatniel Vega Garcia

Edited by Gustavo Camarillo

 

Por Al Serrato

Hace muchos años, cuando era más joven y mucho menos sabio, decidí que sería un buen proyecto de padre e hijo invertir en un coche antiguo que pudiera restaurar. (Nota para los padres: es mucho mejor encontrar algo que les guste a tus hijos que al revés). Así que, después de buscar, y teniendo en cuenta mi escaso presupuesto, encontré un Mustang convertible del 87 que, en general, se encontraba en buenas condiciones. No me resultó difícil imaginar que, con un poco de esfuerzo y un sitio web especializado en piezas de Mustang, podría hacer que este coche tuviera calidad de sala de exposición en poco tiempo.

Después de que la novedad desapareciera, y el interés de mis hijos disminuyera de poco a nada, me encontré con que tenía un proyecto solitario entre manos que tenía esa molesta costumbre de progresar negativamente. Así es. No importaba cuántos elementos tachara de la lista de tareas, se seguían añadiendo más. Y descubrí que las cosas siempre pasaban de buenas a malas, de funcionar a estar rotas, de estar limpias a estar sucias. Los interruptores de las ventanas que funcionaban un día, dejaban de funcionar al siguiente. Los motores que hacen que las ventanas se muevan suavemente hacia arriba y hacia abajo comenzaron a rechinar y luego se detuvieron. Los fusibles se fundieron, una y otra vez. Sorprendentemente, el proceso nunca funcionaba al revés. No importaba el tiempo que esperara, los interruptores rotos nunca se arreglaban solos. Las piezas agrietadas de las molduras, o una luz trasera rota, nunca se reparaban solas. El óxido en el metal siempre aparecía donde antes no estaba, y nunca daba paso a un metal limpio y brillante. Sí, la ley de la entropía estaba plenamente vigente, y la única manera de revertir ese proceso era invertir tiempo, energía y dinero.

Esto, por supuesto, no es una sorpresa para cualquiera que haya tenido algo. Tampoco es una sorpresa para quien haya considerado el funcionamiento de la naturaleza. Los científicos nos dicen que esta ley -la entropía- es una característica del universo. La entropía es, sencillamente, una medida del desorden, y parece que una ley universal está en funcionamiento moviendo todo desde estados de mayor a menor orden. En otras palabras, la naturaleza tiene una dirección particular, y esa dirección es hacia abajo.

El cristianismo y el ateísmo son cosmovisiones que compiten entre sí. Cada una de ellas pretende dar sentido al mundo para explicar cómo son realmente las cosas. Y a pesar de la creciente popularidad del ateísmo, y del creciente desprecio por el cristianismo histórico, la cosmovisión atea es totalmente incapaz de dar sentido al mundo. En relación con la entropía, el ateísmo debe explicar por qué la “evolución” de la vida ha escapado a esta ley universal. ¿Cómo es que seres humanos increíblemente complejos evolucionaron a partir de formas de vida inferiores? Cuando el ADN se somete a cambios aleatorios, el resultado suele ser letal: se llama cáncer. Pero de alguna manera, insisten los ateos, dado el tiempo suficiente, una simple forma de vida unicelular adquirió las instrucciones necesarias para producir una vida humana completa, instrucciones que deben dirigir perfectamente el ensamblaje y el inter-funcionamiento de docenas de sistemas. Y si eso no fuera suficientemente difícil, ¿cómo puede haber surgido la vida a partir de un material inerte -sin vida-? Si se deja una roca sola durante unos milenios, se acaba teniendo, bueno, una roca.

La cosmovisión cristiana , por el contrario, puede proporcionar esa explicación. El acontecimiento del Big Bang que inició este descenso en el progreso, es el resultado de un ser masivamente poderoso e inmensamente inteligente, que proporcionó las leyes que vemos en la naturaleza, y que escribió las instrucciones que los científicos están empezando a descifrar dentro del ADN. La razón por la que la vida “evolucionó” en la tierra es porque un Diseñador Inteligente la diseñó y proporcionó la fuente de energía para impulsar el proceso. Reconocer la necesidad de esa “primera causa” no es algo anticientífico. De hecho, la ciencia moderna comenzó con la presuposición de que las mentes inteligentes podían desentrañar los misterios de la naturaleza porque estos misterios no eran aleatorios, sino que eran el producto de una mente ordenada, de la inteligencia.

Luchar contra lo evidente, como hacen los ateos, tiene aún menos éxito que luchar contra la entropía. Estarían mejor empleando su tiempo en actividades más productivas.

Recursos recomendados en Español:

Robándole a Dios (tapa blanda), (Guía de estudio para el profesor) y (Guía de estudio del estudiante) por el Dr. Frank Turek

Por qué no tengo suficiente fe para ser un ateo (serie de DVD completa), (Manual de trabajo del profesor) y (Manual del estudiante) del Dr. Frank Turek  

 

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

Al Serrato se licenció en Derecho por la Universidad de California en Berkeley en 1985. Comenzó su carrera como agente especial del FBI antes de convertirse en Fiscal en California, donde sigue trabajando. Una introducción a las obras de CS Lewis despertó su interés por la Apologética, que ha seguido durante las últimas tres décadas. Comenzó a escribir Apologética con J. Warner Wallace y Pleaseconvinceme.com.

Blog Original: https://cutt.ly/8QUxzYS

Traducido por Yatniel Vega García

Editado por Ámbar Porta 

 

INTRODUCCIÓN

En este escrito aprovecho de algunas cuestiones filosóficas y científicas mencionadas en la serie Dark para explicarlas de manera sencilla a personas que tal vez no habían escuchado o que habían usado erróneamente y que de alguna manera guardan relación con la teología cristiana.

Definiendo conceptos

En la serie de Dark se suele hablar de términos como “realidad” o “mundos” para distinguir entre el mundo de Jonas, el mundo de Martha y el mundo de origen. Asimismo, algunos youtuberos que analizaron la serie mencionaron “línea temporal” y “universo”. ¿Pero son todos estos conceptos la misma cosa? Bueno, eso depende del contexto. Déjame mostrarte cómo es que yo distinguiría estos términos y que podrían ayudarte para abordar cuestiones metafísicas relacionadas con la teología o la apologética, tales como los mundos posibles y el multiverso.

Definiré realidad como la suma de todas las cosas reales. En este sentido, la realidad es una categoría o clase más que un estado o atributo.

Por mundo quiero decir la suma total de todo lo que existe, incluidas las entidades abstractas no espaciotemporales. Ahora, si las entidades abstractas existen, entonces, tanto mundo como realidad son lo mismo en el presente contexto.

El universo significa el sistema total espaciotemporal de materia y energía (impersonal), es decir, la suma total de objetos materiales, de alguna manera accesible a los sentidos y a la investigación científica.

En cuanto a la línea temporal, este sería algo relativo. Por ejemplo, la línea temporal puede ser tanto la historia de principio a fin de la realidad como la de cada uno de sus universos que pudiera contener.

Y hablando de universos paralelos, por multiverso me refiero a la hipótesis que habla sobre la existencia de un conjunto de universos como el nuestro. Ahora, dado que establecimos que la realidad o el mundo contienen todas las cosas que son reales, entonces los universos sería más bien un subconjunto dentro de un mundo. Así que la idea de que universos paralelos que están conectados unos con otros como lo plantea la serie de DARK, es, al menos, lógicamente posible (si es físicamente posible, es algo que dejaré a los astrofísicos resolver).

Un mundo posible, es un mundo que podría haber sido diferente al actual, o sea, al mundo en el que nosotros vivimos.

Y si hablamos de mundos posibles, entonces estamos obligados a hablar del realismo modal de David Kellogg Lewis. Su teoría propone principalmente que todos los mundos posibles lógicos son tan reales como nuestro mundo (el mundo real o actual). Los mundos posibles en el realismo modal tienen las siguientes 6 características[1]:

  1. Los mundos posibles existen: son tan reales como nuestro mundo.
  2. Los mundos posibles son el mismo tipo de cosas que nuestro mundo: difieren en el contenido, no en la clase.
  3. Los mundos posibles no pueden reducirse a algo más básico: son entidades irreductibles por derecho propio.
  4. La “actualidad” es indexada. Cuando distinguimos nuestro mundo de otros mundos posibles al afirmar que solo es real, solo queremos decir que es “nuestro” mundo.
  5. Los mundos posibles están unificados por las interrelaciones espaciotemporales de sus partes; Cada mundo está aislado espacialmente de todos los demás mundos.
  6. Los mundos posibles están causalmente aislados unos de otros.

Así que como puedes ver, dado 5 y 6, la serie de Dark estaría en lo incorrecto al hablar de mundos que se interconectan o de un mundo que da origen a otros mundos. Así que lo que realmente sucede en la serie, es que existe un mundo, una sola realidad, donde existen varios universos que se interconectan unos con otros a través de la máquina transuniversal de la que nunca se toman la molestia de describir su funcionamiento.

Libre albedrío

Para hablar de libre albedrío, es necesario definir el determinismo. Tomo la siguiente definición:

El determinismo es la visión de que para cada evento que ocurre, hay condiciones tales que, dadas, nada más podría haber ocurrido. Por cada acontecimiento que ocurre, su ocurrencia fue causada o requerida por factores previos, de manera que, dados esos factores previos, el acontecimiento en cuestión tenía que ocurrir. Una forma de determinismo lo define como la postura de que todo acontecimiento es causado por acontecimientos causales anteriores y las leyes pertinentes son suficientes para la producción de ese acontecimiento. En cualquier momento t, sólo hay un mundo futuro físicamente posible que se puede obtener. Cada evento es el resultado inexorable de una cadena de eventos que conducen a ese evento y son suficientes para él.[2]

Con esto en mente, ahora pasemos a hablar sobre el libre albedrío como es expuesto en la serie. Según DARK (y varios youtuberos que analizaron la serie) no existe el libre albedrío como tal por el simple hecho de que los personajes nunca toman decisiones diferentes a como lo hicieron en el ciclo de tiempo anterior, cada vez que se repite el ciclo de tiempo, todos ellos “eligen” siempre lo mismo, lo que demuestra que el libre albedrío no es más que una ilusión—todo está determinado. Así, el único personaje con libre albedrío en la serie resultó ser Cluadia (al menos la Claudia del último ciclo). Ya que es ella quien logra escoger una opción diferente a como lo habían hechos las anteriores Claudias, y esto da paso a que se rompa el bucle temporal y la serie logra terminar en la forma a como lo hizo.

El problema con esto es que se vuelve incomprensible porque solo en Claudia se aplica el PPA y en los demás personajes no si todo está determinado.[3] Una vez que se repite el ciclo, este comienza con las mismas condiciones que el anterior y como todo lo físico está sujeto a las leyes de la causalidad, pues no hay forma de que las cosas ocurran de diferente manera[4].

Pero regresemos a la cuestión del libre albedrío que es lo que nos compete aquí. Mi mayor problema es la definición que toman de libre albedrío, que podría ser como sigue:

Las criaturas libres tienen la capacidad de elegir entre alternativas que compiten entre sí, y realmente podrían elegir una u otra de las alternativas.

Como ustedes pueden ver, en Dark se confunde el libre albedrío libertariano con el principio de posibilidades alternas. La única relación que existe entre ambos es que el PPA es suficiente para el LAL, pero no necesario. Y aunque existen muchas versiones del LAL, considero que la siguiente es correcta:

La libertad [libertaria] no requiere la habilidad de elegir de otra manera que no sea como uno lo hace. […] lo que es crítico para el libre albedrío [libertariano] no es la capacidad de elegir de manera diferente en circunstancias idénticas, sino más bien no ser causado a hacer algo por causas distintas a uno mismo.[5]

Creo que esta versión del libre albedrío es correcta porque las ilustraciones de Harry Frankfurt son demoledoras para demostrar que la libertad (libertariana) no requiere de la habilidad de escoger diferente a la manera que la persona lo hace:

Consideremos a un hombre que, sin saberlo, tiene su cerebro alambrado con electrodos controlados por un científico loco. El científico, quien apoya a Barack Obama, decide que va activar los electrodos para hacer al hombre votar por Obama si el hombre entra en la casilla para votar por Mitt Romney. Por otro lado, si él elige votar por Obama, entonces el científico no va a activar los electrodos. Supongamos, entonces, que el hombre entra en la casilla de votación y presiona el botón para botar por Obama. En ese caso parece que el hombre vota libremente por Obama. ¡Aun si no estaba dentro de su poder el hacer nada diferente![6]

Si aplicamos esta ilustración a los personajes de Dark, podemos concluir que no se requiere que ellos escojan de otra manera a como lo hicieron en los ciclos pasados para que puedan tener libre albedrío (al menos libre albedrío libertariano).

Infinitos actuales

La última cuestión filosófica de la que quiero hablar es el concepto de infinito utilizado en la serie. En el mundo de Dark, tanto en el universo de Jonas como en el de Martha, el tiempo se ha repetido una y otra vez infinidad de veces desde el pasado. Por supuesto, esto es posible puesto que el mundo de Dark adopta la teoría B del tiempo, donde el flujo del tiempo es solo una ilusión y que tanto el pasado, el presente y el futuro son igualmente reales, que el tiempo no tiene tensión, es decir, el devenir temporal no es una característica objetiva de la realidad. Por eso es por lo que, en el último capítulo de la tercera temporada, cuando Claudia se encuentra con Adán, le dice lo siguiente: “Lo que ha ocurrido hasta ahora ha sucedido una infinidad de veces, pero este momento entre tú y yo aquí, es la primera vez que ocurre”. Pero en una teoría A del tiempo, donde el devenir del tiempo es una característica objetiva del tiempo, esto es metafísicamente imposible.

Primero definamos lo que es un infinito potencial y uno actual:

El infinito potencial es la concepción de infinito como un proceso. Este proceso se construye empezando por los primeros pasos (por ejemplo 1, 2, 3 en la construcción del conjunto de los números naturales) que se refieren a una concepción acción. Repetir estos pasos (por la adición de 1 repetidamente) al infinito, requiere de la interiorización de estas acciones en un proceso. El infinito actual es el objeto mental que se obtiene de la encapsulación de este proceso.

…el infinito potencial se percibe como una transformación que se repite sin fin, en donde pueden generarse tantos elementos del proceso como se quiera. Por otra parte, el infinito actual hace referencia a una cosa terminada, un objeto estático que puede construirse a partir de un proceso.[7]

La relevancia filosófica de esta distinción es que algunos filósofos argumentan que el infinito actual no puede existir en la realidad. Por ejemplo, el filósofo medieval Al Gazali argumento a favor de la existencia del universo. Según Gazali, la serie de acontecimientos pasados fue formada al añadir un acontecimiento tras otro. La serie de acontecimientos pasados es como una secuencia de piezas de dominós cayendo una tras otra hasta que la última pieza que cae hoy es alcanzada. Pero él argumenta que ninguna serie formada por añadir un miembro tras otro puede ser actualmente infinita, pues uno no puede pasar por un número infinito de elementos a la vez.

William Lane Craig nos da el ejemplo de contar hasta el infinito:

No importa cuán alto uno pueda contar, siempre habrá una infinidad de números que contar. Si no es posible contar hasta o infinito, ¿cómo sería posible contar a partir del infinito? Sería como si alguien alegase haber hecho un contaje regresivo de todos los números negativos, terminando en cero: …, -3, -2, -1, 0. Eso parece una locura. Pues, antes de que él pueda contar 0, necesitaría contar -1 y, antes de contar -1, necesitaría contar -2, y así sucesivamente, de regreso al infinito. Antes que cualquier número pudiese ser contado, una infinidad de números tendrá que ser contada primero. Uno acaba de ser arrastrado cada vez más y más en el pasado, a tal punto que no es posible contar ningún número más.

Pero entonces, la última pieza del dominó jamás podría caer, si un número infinito de piezas tuviese que caer primero. Por lo tanto, hoy, nunca podría llegar. ¡Pero, obviamente, que aquí estamos! Eso muestra que la serie de acontecimientos pasados debe ser finita y debe tener un comienzo.[8]

Así que, si que, si la Teoría A del tiempo es correcta, esa escena donde Claudia se encuentra con Adán nunca llegaría a darse en primer lugar, porque no puedes pasar por una cadena de eventos infinitos desde el pasado hasta el presente.

Otra paradoja muy interesante que demuestra lo absurdo de esto, es la paradoja del ángel de la muerte propuesta por Alexander Pruss y Robert Koons[9]. De acuerdo con la paradoja, supón que existe una cantidad infinita de ángeles de la muerte. Digamos que tú estás vivo a la media noche. El ángel de la muerte núm. 1 te matará a la 1:00 a.m., si todavía estás vivo a esa hora. El ángel de la muerte núm. 2 te matará a la 12:30 a.m., si todavía está vivo en ese entonces. El ángel de la muerte núm. 3 te matará a la 12:15 a.m., y así sucesivamente. Una situación como esa parece obviamente concebible, dada la posibilidad de un número realmente infinito de cosas, más lleva a una imposibilidad: tú no puedes sobrevivir después de la media noche y, aun así, no puedes ser asesinado por ningún ángel de la muerte en ningún momento.

Este argumento se puede formular de la siguiente manera y es utilizado para argumentar a favor del pasado finito del universo:

  1. Un conjunto formado por adicción sucesiva no puede ser un infinito actual.
  2. La serie temporal de acontecimientos es un conjunto formado por adicción sucesiva.
  3. Por lo tanto, la serie temporal de acontecimientos no puede ser un infinito actual.

CONCLUSIÓN

A pesar de todas las preguntas que podrían haberse dejado sin responder en Dark, así como el uso impreciso de las teorías del tiempo y de algunos conceptos filosóficos, eso no amerita que sea mala, al contrario, jugar con las imposibilidades lógicas y metafísicas siempre le dará ese toque maravilloso a las obras de ciencia ficción, y más si se pueden utilizar de referencia para explicar algunos conceptos de filosofía que de otra manera sería aburrido para para el lector ajeno a estos temas.

Notas

[1] https://es.wikipedia.org/wiki/Realismo_modal (consultado el 29 de julio del 2020).

[2] W. L. Craig and J. P. Moreland, Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview, p. 280.

[3] De acuerdo con los expertos en comentarios de YouTube, los personajes que existen debido a ellos mismos por culpa del bucle (abuelos y nietos son la misma persona) no poseen libre albedrío, solo los personajes “originales” que son del universo de origen pueden tener libre albedrío. Por supuesto, lo curioso es que esta explicación hace nada para proveer dicha distinción a un nivel ontológico.

[4] Existe otra explicación para que Claudia pudiera elegir de forma diferente con el transcurso de los ciclos: la indeterminación o que al menos el universo tiene un cierto grado de indeterminación. Lo que significaría que con cada ciclo que pasa, este sería diferente al anterior en un grado micro, pero da la posibilidad de que después de millones de ciclos exista uno que será muy diferente a comparación de los anteriores. Puedes ver esta explicación con más detalle aquí: https://youtu.be/2M4hJsSArF8

[5] https://es.reasonablefaith.org/question-answer/P270/el-libre-albedrio/?fbclid=IwAR3ugT8Yyvsx-8kV2YoxR-L1lLFD0huewXPyrzuU7yfSvEroiFWdKwRmOfQ (consultado el 29 de julio del 2020).

[6] Ibid.

[7] ROA FUENTES, Solange y OKTAC, Asuman. El infinito potencial y actual: descripción de caminos cognitivos para su construcción en un contexto de paradojas. Educ. mat [online]. 2014, vol.26, n.1 [citado 2020-07-29], pp.73-101. Disponible en: http://www.scielo.org.mx/scielo.php?script=sci_arttext&pid=S1665-58262014000100004&lng=es&nrm=iso. ISSN 1665-5826

[8] https://www.reasonablefaith.org/writings/popular-writings/existence-nature-of-god/the-kalam-cosmological-argument/ (consultado el 29 de julio del 2020).

[9] http://robkoons.net/media/83c9b25c56d629ffffff810fffffd524.pdf (consultado el 29 de julio del 2020).

Recursos recomendados en Español:

Robándole a Dios (tapa blanda), (Guía de estudio para el profesor) y (Guía de estudio del estudiante) por el Dr. Frank Turek

Por qué no tengo suficiente fe para ser un ateo (serie de DVD completa), (Manual de trabajo del profesor) y (Manual del estudiante) del Dr. Frank Turek 

 


Jairo Izquierdo es miembro del equipo de Social Media y autor para la organización cristiana Cross Examined.  Estudia filosofía y teología, siendo su actual foco de estudio la lógica clásica, epistemología, doctrinas cristianas y filosofía del lenguaje.  Es cofundador de Filósofo Cristiano. Es miembro en la Christian Apologetics Alliance y director de alabanza en la iglesia cristiana bautista Cristo es la Respuesta en Puebla, México.

Por Shadow To Light

Uno de los argumentos centrales del movimiento del Nuevo Ateismo insiste en que la ciencia y la religión son «incompatibles”. Los científicos no deben ser religiosos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, se supone que deben abandonar su religión. El argumento es convincente solo para nuevos ateos, simplemente porque es más un tema de conversación para su propaganda anti-religiosa que cualquier tipo de argumento sólido. De hecho, podemos decir que es solo un tema de conversación debido a la naturaleza injustificada selectiva de la comparación. Es decir, si la ciencia es incompatible con la religión, ¿no podría ser también incompatible con otras formas de expresión humana?

Jerry Coyne recientemente escribió un post racionalizando su uso de ad hominems  y el lenguaje inflamatorio:

¿Sabes qué? Me importa un pepino el tono de las declaraciones. Esto es exactamente lo que es de esperar en los sitios web (no en revistas académicas, nota), en un caso que no es puramente académico, sino político. [….] las invectivas del DI me resbalan por la espalda. Hubo un tiempo en ellos -yo creo que fue William Dembski-, que publicaron una foto de mí junto a una de Herman Munster, señalando el parecido.

Con el tiempo la quitaron, pero no me molestó en absoluto. La sátira es una de las armas en esta batalla entre la racionalidad y la superstición.

Claro. En política, la invectiva y la sátira tienen un lugar. En lo político, se busca cambiar la opinión y el comportamiento con el uso de invectivas, la sátira, y otras formas de propaganda. Pero aquí está la cosa.

Este enfoque es incompatible con el enfoque científico. En la ciencia, podemos cambiar opiniones con los resultados experimentales. Cambiamos de opinión con la evidencia científica. Al tratar de comprender cómo la comunidad científica llegó a aceptar la idea de que el ADN era el material genético, sólo tenemos que tener en cuenta algunos de los famosos experimentos que demostraron esto. La invectiva y la sátira no jugaron un papel.

El mismo Coyne reconoce la diferencia cuando escribe: “Esto es exactamente lo que es de esperar en los sitios web (no en revistas académicas, nota), en un caso que no es puramente académico, sino político”.

Sitios web, revistas no académicas.

No es puramente académico, sino político.

En otras palabras, la ciencia y la política son incompatibles. En las ciencias cambiamos opiniones con los resultados experimentales y en la política cambiamos opiniones con la invectiva y la sátira. La ciencia cambia de opinión, apelando a la razón, Mientras la política cambia de opiniones mediante la manipulación de las emociones.

Ahora, recordemos que los nuevos ateos argumentan que los científicos no deben ser religiosos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, se supone que abandonará su religión. La misma lógica también significaría que los científicos no se suponga que sean políticos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, deben abandonar toda postura y actividad política. Los científicos, y todos los que valoran la ciencia, deben ser completamente apolíticos. 

Por supuesto, El Nuevo Ateísmo, por su propia naturaleza, es político. Lo que significa que El Nuevo ateísmo es incompatible con la ciencia.  Los Nuevos Ateos nunca lo admitirían, dado que su movimiento es puramente político y no tiene ningún compromiso con la razón.

 


Traducido por Jorge Gil Calderón

Blog Original: https://bit.ly/2Y1Aq3s

By William Lane Craig

SUMMARY

Whether God is timeless or temporal depends on whether an A-Theory or a B-Theory of time is correct, where the former presents temporal facts and the latter only timeless facts. Given the superiority of the A-Theory, it follows that God is temporal. But since the Special Theory of Relativity relativizes simultaneity to reference frames, the question arises of what “now” is God’s “now.” To answer that question, we must distinguish between time and our measurements of time. Relativity concerns only measured time and therefore does not affect God’s actual time. How does God’s time relate to measured time? Contra Alan Padgett, God’s time must coincide with a measured time, most plausibly the cosmic time of the General Theory of Relativity.

Introduction

While some of the traditional attributes of God, such as omnipotence or omniscience (particularly divine foreknowledge) have been exhaustively—and one is tempted to say almost exhaustively—analyzed and defended in recent philosophical literature, other divine attributes such as the eternity of God have received scant and generally superficial analysis. [1] Current discussions of the eternity of God have for the most part been conducted in almost complete ignorance of the philosophy of space and time and without any deep knowledge of the theory of relativity and its analysis of time [2] —a notable deficiency, when one thinks about it, for how can one hope to formulate an adequate doctrine of the eternity of God and its relation to time without taking into account what modern philosophy and science have to say about time?

Now Alan Padgett, a PhD candidate under Richard Swinburne, has attempted to remedy that lack by presenting, in full conversation with philosophical and scientific discussions of time, a view of divine eternity that he characterizes as “relative timelessness.” [3] As someone who has recently been working in this very area, I wish to endorse the direction in which Padgett is moving and offer some refinements to this view.

The Eternal Eternity of God: Theory A vs. Theory B of Time

Padgett rejects the classical Plotinian-Augustinian analysis of divine eternity in terms of timeless existence, a view he calls “absolute timelessness.” He regards the classical analysis as inadequate because God, in order to sustain created things, which are always changing in their ontological state, must change in his activity and therefore cannot be timeless.

What Padgett’s article does not make clear, however, is that this line of argument only carries through if one has previously committed oneself to an A-theory of time. [4] According to the A-theorist, temporal becoming is a real, objective feature of the universe; transience is essential to the nature of time, a truth expressed metaphorically by saying that time “flows.” The temporal properties of events cannot be adequately analyzed in terms of prior , simultaneous , and posterior alone, but must include references to the past , present , and future , which are not merely deictic expressions but are irreducibly temporal. The present represents the edge of becoming, and future events merely do not exist yet , but do not exist at all . By contrast, according to the B-theorist, temporal becoming is mind-dependent and purely subjective. Time does not flow, nor do things come into being, except in the sense that at one moment we are aware of them after not having been at an earlier moment. Simultaneous things with different moments on the timeline are equally existent and interrelated to each other by the prior, simultaneous and subsequent relationships to which past, present and future can be reduced. Anything that, from our perspective, existed, exists or will exist in the universe, simply exists (without temporality).

By contrast, on the A-theory of time, the concept of a timeless God who is actually related to the world seems incoherent. Since future states of the universe do not actually exist, God cannot be causing them (even timelessly) to exist; otherwise, they would in fact exist at their respective times. The same holds for past states of the universe. Thus, Aquinas’s argument that God causes timeless things to happen at their respective times only succeeds in showing that things caused by time need not exist eternally, and in fact betrays a B-theoretic view. [5] Even if God immutably wills from eternity that a temporal event exist, there must be attached to that will an exercise of divine causality at the time of the thing’s creation for it to actually happen at that time rather than existing timelessly at that time. The only way to avoid this conclusion would be to deny with Aquinas that God is really related to the world, a totally implausible system of motion that depends on an elaborate Aristotelian metaphysics. [6]

It can be plausibly argued, I think, that the A-theory of time is philosophically and theologically superior to the B-theory. Philosophically, one should agree with D. H. Mellor that “time is such a striking aspect of reality that only the most compelling argument justifies denying it: namely, that the dynamical view of time is contradictory and therefore cannot be true” [7] and then proceed to show that in fact all such attempts to provoke a contradiction, such as McTaggart’s, fail, [8] leaving us secure in our naturally intuitive understanding of the A-theory. No B-theorist, on the other hand, has successfully answered, in my view, the charge that his theory is incoherent because mental dependence on physical becoming requires real becoming in the subjective contents of consciousness. [9] In favor of theory A, one could argue that it offers the most adequate analysis of personal identity [10] and that the temporality of our language and experience is inescapable. [11]

Theologically, there seems to be one decisive reason for Christian theists to reject the B-theory, namely, that it cannot give an adequate analysis of the biblical doctrine of creatio ex nihilo . In the B-theory, creatio ex nihilo is reduced to the ontological dependence of creation on God and the space-time continuum with an edge or boundary. But creation as a whole is co-eternal with God in the sense that it exists as timelessly as He does. There is no state of affairs in the present world that consists in God existing alone without creation. But such an analysis is a wholly inadequate understanding of the biblical doctrine that the created order came into existence and was created by God. Although Aquinas (unlike Bonaventure) thought that one could not philosophically prove this aspect of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo , he was firmly committed to it on the basis of revelation, a fact that contemporary theologians, who sometimes appeal to Aquinas to justify their undue reliance on temporal creativity ex nihilo , tend to forget. [12]

Padgett’s argument against divine timelessness, then, is valid only if the case for an A-theory is successful. What the reader of Padgett’s paper will not realize is that Padgett himself is fully aware of this point and argues for the superiority of the A-theory in his unpublished thesis. On this point, therefore, we are in fundamental agreement.

God’s time and ours

If the A-theory of time is correct, then, and God is in time, the question naturally arises in the context of the theory of relativity: “Whose time is God in?” According to that theory, events that are present to an observer in one inertial frame may be future to an observer in another inertial frame. Certain events will even occur in reverse temporal order relative to some frames compared to others. An observer at rest relative to an observer making a high-speed round trip will experience moments of time or “nows” for which there literally are no correlated simultaneous moments in the traveler’s experience. According to Einstein, neither of these perspectives is privileged, and therefore there is no absolute “now” in the universe. Absolute simultaneity has been banished from the universe in favor of simultaneity relative to a frame of reference. For example, no event occurs “now” in an absolute sense on the planet Neptune or even on the other side of the earth. For observers in relatively mobile reference frames, at this same space-time point they will draw different planes of simultaneity in space-time and thus measure different events, say, on Neptune, as occurring in their respective “nows.” But what is God’s “now”?

Ontological time and measured time

It is to the credit of Padgett’s work that he has cut this Gordian knot by distinguishing between “time” and “measured time.” [13] Time itself, according to Padgett, has to do with God’s eternal duration; measured time is clock time, time according to some metric. Padgett argues that while God is in time, he is not in any measured time, and therefore his “now” is not to be identified with any of the relative “nows” of measured time.

This distinction between ontological time and measured (or empirical) time seems to me to be an extremely important insight, which is a healthy counterweight to the universally repeated and extravagant claims that TRE has forced us to abandon: the classical views of time and space. [14] This erroneous inference rests precisely on the failure to draw the kind of distinction that Padgett has emphasized. That failure can be laid at Einstein’s door. It seems astonishing to me that anyone reading Einstein’s 1905 paper could think that Einstein proved that there is no absolute simultaneity, and that therefore time is relative to reference frames. [15] For the whole theory depends on the acceptance of Einstein’s arbitrary (and, indeed, highly counterintuitive) definition of simultaneity, [16] together with a philosophical positivism of Machian provenance [17] according to which a notion like absolute simultaneity is meaningless if it is empirically undetectable. Since the ether frame of 19th century physics could not be detected empirically, Einstein dismissed it as meaningless, along with his absolute simultaneity, which referred to events occurring simultaneously in the ether frame. By redefining simultaneity in terms of the light signal timing method, Einstein was able to give empirical meaning to the notion of simultaneity, but the simultaneity that emerges from the theory is relative due to the invariant speed of light. Since light signals are measured as having the speed c regardless of the motion of the sender or receiver of the signals, two relatively moving observers will measure the same event occurring at different times, which goes against the traditional notion of simultaneity. [18]

Anyone who is not a positivist, and therefore rejects Einstein’s definitions, would regard these relatively soulful observers as deluded because of the nature of their measurements, which cannot detect real time. [19] In a real sense, he would not regard Einstein’s theory as a theory about time and space at all, but, as Frank put it, as “a system of hypotheses about the behavior of light rays, rigid bodies, and mechanisms, from which new results about this behavior can be derived.” [20] Trapped in our locally moving frames, we may be forced to measure time by devices that are inadequate to detect real time, but that by no means implies that there is no such time. The fact that uniformly moving clocks run slowly says more about our clocks than about the nature of time. Thus, Einstein’s theory can be regarded as pragmatically useful and scientifically fruitful without having to regard absolute simultaneity and absolute time as abolished.

One might think that Einstein’s positivism was simply a historically accidental feature of the theory, but it is not part of the philosophical foundations of that theory. Such an attitude, however, would be mistaken. As J.S. Bell points out, it is primarily this philosophical positivism that serves to distinguish the Einsteinian interpretation of lavTRE from the Lorentzian interpretation, which differentiates between ontological time and measured time:

The difference in philosophy is this. Since it is experimentally impossible to tell which of two systems of uniform motion is really at rest, Einstein declares that the notions of “really at rest” and “really in motion” are meaningless. For him, only the relative motion of two or more objects in uniform motion is real. Lorentz, on the other hand, preferred to see that there does indeed exist a real state of rest, defined by the “ether,” even though the laws of physics conspire to prevent us from identifying it experimentally. The facts of physics do not force us to accept one philosophy rather than the other. [21]

Since the Lorentzian interpretation of the TER is empirically equivalent to Einstein’s interpretation, the only way the latter can rule out the former is by a positivist critique of notions of absolute simultaneity, and so on. According to Lawrence Sklar,

“Certainly the original arguments for the relativist view are riddled with verificationist presuppositions about meaning, etc. And despite Einstein’s later denial of the verificationist view, no one to my knowledge has provided an adequate account of the foundations of relativity that is not verificationist in essence.” [22] “I see no way to reject the old compensatory ether theories […] without invoking a verificationist criticism of one sort or another.” [23]

Now this constitutes a truly serious drawback of Einstein’s interpretation. As Healey observes, although positivists tried to restrict the content of scientific theories in order to ensure that they were meaningful, “more recently positivism has come under such sustained attack that opposition has become almost orthodoxy in the philosophy of science.” [24] Philosophers of religion need not be reminded of the untenability of positivism in view of their radical critique of religious language, which would regard Padgett’s distinction between God’s time and our time as cognitively meaningless.

Since God is in time, therefore, it is evident that His is not the time that is determined by Einstein’s operational definitions; subject to dilation, the relativity of simultaneity, and the reversal of events. Rather, God’s time is true A-series time, determined by the succession of events in divine consciousness and activity and characterized by the absolute “now” of the present and the edge of becoming. His is, to borrow D.H. Mellor’s phrase, “Real Temporality.”

So I think it’s rather unfortunate that Padgett chose to call his view “relative timelessness,” because it is precisely the opposite. It is God who exists in true ontological time, while finite observers, restricted to our locally moving reference frames dependent on the light signal timing of clocks, have to make do with our manufactured measured time. Contrary to Padgett, ordinary use of time concepts cannot justify calling God relatively timeless, since our intuitive view of time is an A-theoretic view, and this is precisely the time in which God lives. Thus, the view Padgett presents is better labeled “Real Temporality.”

God’s time and cosmic time

But how does God’s time relate to our own? Padgett answers that while we are in God’s time, God is not in any measured time. But this answer seems to me to be factually false. From the perspective of God in the real time of the A-series, there is an absolute present in which he is now aware of what is happening in the universe, and he is now causally causing the events in the universe. But if, as we saw in our critique of divine timelessness, God’s causally sustaining the universe in being is simultaneous with the events being sustained, then there must be an absolute cosmic “now” that describes the state of the universe as it is present to God. Future events for this moment do not exist at all, since God has not yet caused them. But is there a frame of reference in the universe that produces a measured time that can be naturally associated with the succession of such moments? Yes, there is. It is not, in fact, the inertial frame of any spatially local observer, but the reference frame of the cosmic expansion of space itself. The relativity of simultaneity depends on the assumption that there is no preferred reference frame; but if there is a preferred frame, as the Lorentzian interpretation would have it, then the relations of simultaneity in it would be absolute, and relativity would apply to all other frames. But the frame associated with cosmic expansion seems naturally suited to such a privileged position. Michael Shallis explains:

However, it is also possible to take a single clock as a standard, to define a universal time coordinate and to relativize everything to it […] Of course, the choice of a coordinate time is to some extent arbitrary; in principle, one could take any clock as a standard. But in a cosmological context, it is natural to take as a standard a clock whose motion is typical or representative of the motion of matter in general, one that simply “advances,” so to speak, with the general expansion of the universe. [25]

We must not forget that Einstein proposed his Special Theory long before cosmic expansion was discovered, so that in the absence of the characterless and dying ether, there seemed to be no empirical basis for positing any universal frame beyond the multitude of locally moving frames. But with the discovery that the universe is expanding, it became possible to imagine a universal frame of reference by imagining observers associated with fundamental particles (i.e., galaxies or galaxy clusters) having mutual recessional velocities. In fact, the “gas” constituted by these fundamental particles is at rest relative to the expansion of cosmic space and is therefore an ether. As early as 1920, Eddington acknowledged that the General Theory of Relativity postulated a kind of cosmic time, but he objected that such cosmic time was unknowable and therefore irrelevant to observers in moving local frames. [26] Within a few years, however, the expansion of the universe predicted by Einstein’s field equations (minus the cosmological constant) had been confirmed by observational astronomy, thus providing a sort of cosmic clock that the abandonment of the aether theory seemed to have served no practical purpose. Of course, it might still be objected that this universal time is unknowable and therefore irrelevant. But not only does this objection seem to be infected with a defunct verificationist attitude, it does not even seem to be true. Recent observations have revealed an apparent anisotropy in the cosmic microwave background radiation that is due to the motion of the earth relative to the cosmic reference frame, resulting in what has been characterized as a “new aether wind” of about 360 kilometers per second. [27] Comments by P.C. W. Davies,

At any given location in the universe, there is only one reference frame in which the universe is expanding isotropically. This privileged reference frame defines a privileged time scale (the time indicated by a clock at rest in that frame). Two separate locations have their privileged reference frames in mutual motion, due to the expansion of the universe. However, the time measured by the entire collection of imaginary standard clocks is obviously correlated such that the global condition (e.g., the average separation of two galaxies) of the universe appears the same at times equal to those recorded by each privileged clock (assuming they are all correctly synchronized). Fortunately, the Earth moves very slowly relative to the local privileged frame in our vicinity of the universe, so Earth time is a fairly accurate measure of cosmic time. [28]

Not only, then, is there cosmic time, but we even have a pretty good idea of ​​what time it is.

Given the existence of this cosmic time, I believe that the moments of God’s actual time, the A-series—while perhaps not identical to the moments of measured cosmic time—do coincide. God’s ontological time clearly exceeds the cosmic time by which the former could have preceded the latter (imagine God leading creation by counting “1, 2, 3, … fiat lux !”), but once cosmic time comes into existence, its moments would coincide with the moments of actual time. How could they fail to do so? If the duration of the universe is measured in cosmic time at 15 billion years from the singularity, isn’t the duration of God’s creative activity in actual time the same duration? In God’s “now” the universe has (present time) certain specific and unique properties, for example, a certain radius, a certain density, a certain background temperature, etc., but in the cosmic “now” it has all the identical properties, and so it is with each successive “now.” Is it not obvious that these “nows” coincide and designate the same present?

Perhaps we can state this consideration more formally by the following principle:

P : For any recurrent, constantly changing universe U and time intervals x , y large enough to allow change, if the physical description of U at x is the same as the physical description of U at y , then x and y coincide.

Since in real time there is a temporal interval or duration during which a certain physical description of the universe is true, and since in cosmic time there is a similar interval, it follows from P that those intervals of real and cosmic time coincide. Note that the argument makes no reference to any particular metrication of time and therefore does not depend on it. It seems to me, then, that real time and cosmic time should naturally be regarded as coinciding since the beginning of cosmic time.

Padgett’s objections to this understanding of the relationship of God’s time to measured time appear to be rather weak. He first objects that God is not subject to the laws of nature, as anything in measured time must be. He argues that since God acts freely rather than uniformly and has the power to alter the laws of nature, he cannot be in measured time. But why could not God’s time contain its own intrinsic metric, as Newton believed, that physical clocks provide a more or less “sensible” measure? [29] In this case, an ideal physical clock would measure God’s time. Furthermore, the premise that anything in measured time must be subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur. It is the measuring instrument , i.e. the clock , that must be subject to the laws of nature, not the object of measurement, which could be a totally random process. To say that 15 billion years ago God created the universe is not to say that God is subject to the laws of planetary motion, but simply to apply to God’s time a conventional metric that marks a duration equal to the duration of the earth’s orbit around the sun. That is to say that the duration during which God thought or did something is equal to, say, the duration it would take the earth to complete a certain number of orbits. Even on a purely mundane level, global proper time near the singularity is not a direct count of simple, real phenomena, since the earth will not have actually completed, say, 1010 orbits in the last 1010 years and even a cesium atomic clock would not have ticked at very early intervals. Rather, global proper time is an elaborate mathematical extrapolation of physical phenomena. [30] Similarly, any arbitrarily chosen metric can be applied to the duration of God or the universe.

Padgett anticipates such an objection, supposing that the universe might be thought of as acting as a kind of clock to measure the length of God’s time. But let’s be quite clear about this, for the universe does not merely act as a clock for God. The universe is a clock; it is God’s clock. For example, some conventional unit of God’s time might be the time it takes for the radius of the universe to increase by a certain factor. Padgett retorts that it does not follow that because two events e1 and e2 are one hour apart in one frame of reference, they are one hour apart in God’s time. He appeals to time dilation between relatively moving frames to show that the duration between two identical events can be measured diversely. But the analogy fails here, for we are not comparing two relatively moving frames using light signals to synchronize their respective clocks. Since God is actually related to the universe and not moving relative to it, there is no basis for any relativity of simultaneity between His present and the cosmic present. God is a disembodied Mind that uses a physical clock.

Padgett objects that cosmic time is contingent and applies only to our universe. We cannot, therefore, suppose that it applies to anything beyond it. But we have no reason, biblical or philosophical, to think that there are other universes. Parsimony justifies the assumption that ours is the only universe. In that case, it only follows that actual time and cosmic time contingently coincide ; there are possible worlds in which they do not. [31] But why is that an objection? Since God’s decision to create was free, cosmic time is essentially contingent; indeed, I should say that even actual time is contingent. [32] But since cosmic time exists, there is no objection to holding that God’s time contingently coincides with it for the duration of the cosmos.

Padgett’s second objection to this view is that measured time is relative to a particular frame of reference, which need not apply to God. He argues that because God transcends space, his life need not occur in our four-dimensional space-time continuum. Therefore, his life is not limited to the temporal dimension of our space-time.

This objection raises some interesting questions about divine omnipresence, [33] which we can give up. One might also question whether the objection has sufficient insight into the difference between parameter time and coordinate time. [34] In Newtonian mechanics, time functions as a parameter, which is entirely independent of space. However, in the theory of relativity, time functions not only as a parameter, but also as a coordinate that is joined with spatial coordinates. However, that theory is susceptible to reformulation entirely in terms of parameter time. One might therefore argue that God is in measured time, but that means therefore parameter time, not coordinate time, so that God’s independence from space is preserved. However, the essential point to be made is that God’s time can be measured by coordinate time without His being also measured by spatial coordinates, because on the understanding I have proposed, moments of ontological time can be thought of as coinciding with moments of measured time without being identical to them. Thus, even if it is true that a being whose duration is measured exclusively by coordinate time must also have spatial coordinates, it does not follow that a being whose duration in ontological time coincides with its duration in measured time must also be in space. Again, the fact that this coincidence is contingent constitutes no objection, but it is in fact implied by traditional theism.

It seems to me, therefore, that Padgett’s view needs to be refined with respect to the relationship between ontological time and measured time, and hence between God’s time and our own. Real time is the time of the A-series in which God thinks and acts and in which things come into being; the moments of this time coincide from the beginning of the universe with the moments of cosmic time determined by ideal stationary clocks with respect to the expansion of space itself.

Conclusion

I believe, therefore, that Padgett has gone a long way toward formulating a philosophically sound and scientifically informed doctrine of divine eternity that is also faithful to biblical revelation. The philosophical and theological grounds for preferring an A-theory of time also provide justification for rejecting the Plotine-Augustinian doctrine of divine timelessness because that theory seems incompatible with the real relationship of a timeless God to the world. God thinks and acts in real time—that is, the A-series of temporal moments, in which becoming, absolute simultaneity, and absolute “now” exist—and his relationship to time must be characterized as “true temporality.” In contrast, by conventionally defining simultaneity in terms of the light-signal method of clock synchronization and by adopting arbitrary metrics to quantify time, men have developed a measured time, which is extremely malleable to relatively moving timekeepers. Since God is not in any inertial frame, his time, ontological time, is not subject to these effects. However, in our universe, due to its isotropic expansion from an initial singularity, there is cosmic time that records successive moments in the history of the universe. Although ontological time may precede (or succeed) measured cosmic time—whether ontological time has a beginning is an issue we have not sought to judge in this article—nevertheless, the moments of ontological time and cosmic time will coincide for the duration of cosmic time, since they refer to the identical succession of states in the universe. To object that this makes God subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur , since it is our clocks that must be subject. To object that this view traps God in spacetime is equally mistaken, since ontological time only contingently coincides with cosmic time, so that God in ontological time can exist at a time that coincides with a measured moment of time without having to possess coordinate space as well. One of the interesting implications of this understanding is that a Lorentzian rather than an Einsteinian interpretation of the special theory of relativity is correct: there is a preferred reference frame in which light propagates with speed c , and relativistic effects are due to local motion relative to this frame. With these refinements, Padgett’s view of divine eternity appears to be coherent and plausible.

Grades

[1] Note that the literature on divine eternity is so sparse that it did not even merit a mention in Philosophy of Religion: an Annotated Bibliography of Twentieth Century Writings in English (New York: Garland Publishing, 1978).

[2] See, for example. Nelson Pike,  God and Timelessness  (New York: Schocken Books, 1970); Stephen T. Davis,  Logic and the Nature of God  (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1983); Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “Eternity,”  Journal of Philosophy  78 (1981):429-58.

[3] Alan Padgett, “God and Time: Toward a New Doctrine of Divine Timeless Eternity,”  Religious Studies  25 (1989): 209-15); see further idem , “Divine Eternity and the Nature of Time” (Ph.D. thesis, Oxford University, 1988) [now published as  God, Eternity, and the Nature of Time  (New York: St. Martin’s, 1992)].

[4] The distinction between the A and B series of temporal events was originally made by J. M. E. McTaggart,  The Nature of Existence , 2 vols., ed. C. D. Broad (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927; rep. ed.: 1968), Book V, chs. 33; for discussion, see C. D. Broad,  Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy , 2 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1938; rep. ed.: New York: Octagon Books, 1976), 2:265–344. See also Richard Gale, “Introduction” to Section II: “The Static versus the Dynamic Temporal,” in  The Philosophy of Time , ed. R. Gale (London: Macmillan, 1968), pp. 65–85.

[5] On the connection between classical conceptions of divine eternity and a B theory of time, see Wm. L. Craig,  The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez , Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 7 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1988), pp. 116–21; idem, “St. Anselm on Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingency,”  Laval théologique et philosophique  42 (1986):93–104. See also Delmas Lewis, “Eternity, Time and Tenselessness,”  Faith and Philosophy  5 (1988):72–86.

[6] For a brief critique, see Wm. L. Craig, “God, Time, and Eternity,”  Religious Studies 14 (1979):497-503.

[7] D.H. Mellor,  Real Time  (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 5.

[8] See refutation in Paul Horwich,  Asymmetries in Time  (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 26–27. Horwich’s own rejection of A-theory is based on the mistaken view that an A-theory entails the denial of semantic bivalence for contingent future propositions.

[9] Such an objection needs to be formulated more carefully, but is detailed in Milic Capek,  The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics  (Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1961), p. 165; idem, “Introduction,” in  The Concepts of Space and Time , ed. M. Capek, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), p. XLVII; Frederick Ferré, “Grünbaum on Temporal Becoming: A Critique,”  International Philosophical Quarterly  12 (1972):432-33; James A. McGilvray, “A Defense of Physical Becoming,”  Erkenntnis  14 (1979):275-99.

[10] See Ronald C. Hoy, “Becoming and Persons,”  Philosophical Studies  34 (1978):269-80.

[11] See Quentin Smith, “Problems with the New Tenseless Theory of Time,”  Philosophical Studies  52 (1987):371-92 and the literature cited therein.

[12] See, for example, John Polkinghorne, “Cosmology and Creation,” paper presented at the conference “The Origin of the Universe,” Colorado State University, Ft. Collins, Colorado, September 22-25, 1988. The proceedings will probably be published by SUNY Press.

[13] This much-misunderstood distinction was carefully worked out by Newton himself in the Scholium  to the Definitions at the beginning of his  Principia  (Isaac Newton,  Sir Isaac Newton’s ‘Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy’ and his ‘System of the World’,  trans. Andrew Motte, rev. with appendix by Florian Cajori, 2 vols. [Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1966], pp. 6–12). Cf. M. F. Cleugh,  Time and its Importance in Modern Thought  (London: Methuen, 1937), pp. 29–67; Philipp Frank,  Philosophy of Science  (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1957), pp. 140–43; Herbert Dingle, “Time in Philosophy and Physics,”  Philosophy  54 (1979):99–104.

[14] Typical are Hawking’s recent statements: “…the theory of relativity puts an end to the idea of ​​absolute time […] The theory of relativity forces us to fundamentally change our ideas of space and time.” (Stephen Hawking,  A Brief History of Time  [New York: Bantam Books, 1988], pp. 21, 23).

[15] A. Einstein, “On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies,” in  The Principle of Relativity , trans. W. Perrett and GB Jeffery with notes by A. Sommerfield (New York: Dover Publications, 1952), pp. 37-65.

[16] Two spatially separated events are simultaneous if they both occur at the same clock hours as recorded by two synchronized clocks A and B situated respectively at the locations of the events, where A and B are stationary relative to each other and B reads the same as A at the temporal midpoint of the time required for A to send a light signal to B and receive it back. The assumption is that A and B are not moving with reference to the ether-frame, so the travel time of the signal is no longer (or shorter) on the return leg of its journey. Now, clearly, unless one is an operationalist, this is not what is meant by simultaneity, and unless one is a positivist, the underlying assumption of the definition is entirely gratuitous.

[17] The influence of Mach’s positivism on Einstein and his Special Theory of Relativity is widely acknowledged by historians of science, but surprisingly rarely discussed by philosophers exploring the philosophical foundations of that theory. For discussion, see G. Holton, “Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality,” in Ernst Mach: Physicist and Philosopher , Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1970), pp. 167-77; P. Frank, “Einstein, Mach, and Logical Positivism,” in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P. A. Schilpp, Library of Living Philosophers 7 (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1949), pp. 271-86; H. Reichenbach, “The Philosophical Significance of the Theory of Relativity”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 289-311.

[18] For alternative operational definitions of “simultaneity” and “synchronization” that preserve absolute simultaneity, see T. Sjödin, “On the One-Way Velocity of Light and its Possible Measurability”, paper presented at the conference Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory , British Society for the Philosophy of Science, Imperial College, London, September 16–19, 1988.

[19] This is, in fact, the modern Lorentzian interpretation of SRT, which holds that velocity affects our measuring devices, so that moving rods and clocks contract slowly. Such an interpretation does not commit us to a substantive ether, but merely to an ether- frame , i.e. a privileged frame of reference. The fact that the Lorentzian interprets longitudinal contraction and time dilation as not merely apparent but real cannot be cited as a disadvantage of the theory, since the Einsteinian must also postulate real contraction and dilation (see Peter Kroes’ paper “The Physical Status of Time Dilation within the Special Theory of Relativity,” at the conference mentioned in note 18; see also Dennis Dieks, “The `Reality’ of the Lorentz Contraction,” Zeitschrift fur allgemeine Wissenschafts-theorie 15/2). The difference between the two on this point is that the Lorentzian offers some explanation for these effects, while the Einsteinian does not. The decision between a Lorentzian and an Einsteinian interpretation of SRT will probably depend on whether God’s time can plausibly be interpreted to coincide with some coordinate time, which would therefore be the privileged time of the aether frame.

[20] Frank,  Philosophy of Science , p. 140.

[21]  J. S. Bell, “How to Teach Special Relativity,” in  Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics , ed. JS Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 77.

[22] Lawrence Sklar, “Time, reality and relativity,” in  Reduction, Time and Reality , ed. R. Healey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 141.

[23] Ibid., p. 132

[24] R. Healey, “Introduction,” in  Reduction, Time and Reality , p. vii.

[25] Muchael Shallis, “Time and Cosmology,” in  The Nature of Time , ed. Raymond Flood and Michael Lockwood (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp. 68-69.

[26] Arthur Eddington,  Space, Time and Gravitation , Cambridge Science Classics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 168:

In the first place, absolute space and time are restored for cosmic-scale phenomena […] The world taken as a whole has a direction in which it does not curve; that direction gives a kind of absolute time distinct from space. Relativity is reduced to local phenomena; and although this is sufficient for the theory so far described, we are inclined to look at the limitation reluctantly. But we have already insisted that the theory of relativity is not concerned with denying the possibility of absolute time, but with denying that it is concerned with any experimental knowledge that has been found; and we need not be disturbed if the conception of absolute time appears in a new form in a theory of cosmic-scale phenomena, of which no experimental knowledge is yet available.

[27] GF Smoot, MV Gorenstein, and RA Muller, “Detection of Anisotropy in the Cosmic Blackbody Radiation,”  Physical Review Letters  39 (1977): 899.

[28] PCW Davies, “Space-Time Singularities in Cosmology and Black Hole Evaporations,” in  The Study of Time III , ed. JT Fraser, N. Lawrence, and D. Park (Berlin: Springer Verlag, 1978), p. 76. I have corrected spelling errors in the quote.

[29] See Charles W. Misner, Kip S. Thorne, John A. Wheeler, Gravitation (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1973), pp. 813-14. The authors’ attempt to criticize proper global time as inadequately physical fails to appreciate the counterfactual nature of the application of the metric; elapsed time is measured as if an atomic clock were present and running.

[30]  For a helpful discussion see Peter Kroes,  Time: Its Structure and Its Role in Physical Theories , Synthese Library 179 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), p. 49.

[31] By postulating a cosmic rotation of matter, Gödel was able to work out model universes satisfying Einstein’s field equations in which there is no cosmic time (Kurt Gödel, “A Remark about the Relationship between Relativity Theory and Idealistic Philosophy”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 557–62). In such worlds, Padgett’s view would be correct. But in fact, there is cosmic time, and it naturally appears to coincide with real time.

[32] See my “God, Time and Eternity,” pp. 497-503, where I argue that God existing without creation is timeless and that He enters time at its beginning with His creation of the universe. Since creation is a freely willed act of God, the existence of actual time is therefore contingent.

[33] See, for example, Eddington’s observation:

Just as each limited observer has his own particular separation of space and time, so a being coextensive with the world might well have a special separation of space and time natural to him. It is the moment of this being which is here dignified by the title of “absolute.” (Eddington, Space, Time and Gravitation , p. 168)

[34] See Kroes,  Time , pp. 60-96.

 


William Lane Craig is an American Baptist Christian analytic philosopher and theologian. Craig’s philosophical work focuses on the philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and philosophy of time. His theological interests lie in historical Jesus studies and philosophical theology.

Original Blog: http://bit.ly/3aWccf2 

Translated by Jairo Izquierdo

By Max Andrews

Reduplicated preaching is the means to understanding the relationship between the natures of Jesus Christ. When Scripture attributes human qualities to Jesus they must be based on his human nature. Likewise, when Scripture attributes divine qualities to Jesus they must be based on his divine nature.

With this insight, we might be able to solve the problem of the predicates of the Person. The predicate property of the Person is one with respect to nature (i.e. ignorance with humanity and omniscience with divinity — hunger and fatigue with humanity, need with divinity).

But now there is a problem. Once we apply this to Jesus, such predicates as omniscience and ignorance, and sinlessness and humanity seem to be incompatible. A problem with limitations is posed. Is this irremediable? I don’t think so.

Additional Qualifier – We can posit that the divine aspects of Jesus were largely subliminal during his humiliation (his ministry before death). What reasons are there to support this qualifier? In fact, this qualifies Jesus’ humanity even further.

Psychoanalysis has confirmed the existence of a subconscious. This is evident in schizophrenia and in hypnosis. With schizophrenia there is one conscious that is awake and one (or more) that is not, however, the subliminal subconscious can still become a reality. There is one that controls and governs the conscious. With hypnosis, one can be hypnotized and instructed not to look at, for example, a table. If you were instructed to walk to the door, and the table was between you and the door, you would walk around the table, even though you cannot literally see it, you still have the knowledge that it exists in your subconscious.

During the incarnation, the Logos allowed only certain aspects of consciousness into the person of Christ that were compatible with normal human experience. This gives much more light to the genuineness of his temptation, the anointing and filling of the Spirit, the Spirit drawing him into the wilderness, his prayer to the Father (these are not just samples). Jesus, at 3 years old, would not have been contemplating Newton’s infinitesimal calculus or quantum mechanics; he was a genuine Jewish boy growing in wisdom and stature.

So in essence it was a self-limitation of humanity with simultaneous practical divinity in one Person. This is different from Kenotic Christology in that He does not give up certain attributes and no longer possess them. In this view, He still retains all the human and divine aspects of voluntary limitation.

 


Original Blog: http://bit.ly/2nir4jz

Translated by Jorge Gil Calderon

Mientras revisaba uno de los tantos correos que recibimos, en uno de ellos se planteaban dos objeciones en contra del argumento cosmológico Kalam, en específico al argumento ofrecido para Dios como la causa del comienzo del universo. Una versión del argumento cosmológico kalam se puede formular de la siguiente forma:

1. Todo lo que comienza a existir tiene una causa de su existencia.

2. El universo comenzó a existir.

2.1. Argumento basado en la imposibilidad de un infinito actual:

   2.1.1. Un infinito actual no puede existir.

   2.1.2. Una regresión temporal infinita de eventos es un infinito actual.

   2.1.3. Por lo tanto, una regresión temporal infinita de eventos no puede existir.

2.2. Argumento basado en la imposibilidad de la formación de un infinito actual por adición sucesiva:

    2.2.1. Una colección formada por adiciones sucesivas no puede ser actualmente infinita.

    2.2.2. La serie temporal de eventos pasados es una colección formada por adiciones sucesivas.

    2.2.3. Por lo tanto, la serie temporal de eventos pasados no puede ser actualmente infinita.

2.3. Confirmación basada en la expansión del universo.

2.4. Confirmación basada en las propiedades termodinámicas del universo.

3. Por lo tanto, el universo tiene una causa de su comienzo a la existencia.

4. Si el universo tiene una causa de su existencia, entonces existe un Creador personal incausado del universo que, sin la creación, es imprincipiado, inmutable, inmaterial, atemporal, inespacial, y enormemente poderoso.

4.1. Argumento de que la causa del universo es un Creador personal:

   4.1.1. El universo fue creado por un conjunto de condiciones necesarias y suficientes de funcionamiento mecánico o por un agente libre personal.

   4.1.2. El universo no pudo haber sido creado por un conjunto mecánico de condiciones necesarias y suficientes.

   4.1.3. Por lo tanto, el universo fue creado por un agente libre personal.

4.2. Argumento de que el Creador sin la creación es incausado, inprincipiado, inmutable, inmaterial, atemporal, inespacial y enormemente poderoso.

    4.2.1. El Creador es incausado.

       4.2.1.1. No puede existir una regresión temporal infinita de causas (2.1.3, 2.2.3).

    4.2.2. El Creador es imprincipiado.

       4.2.2.1. Cualquier cosa que no esté causada no comienza a existir. (1)

    4.2.3. El Creador es inmutable.

       4.2.3.1. No puede existir una regresión temporal infinita de cambios. (2.1.3, 2.2.3)

    4.2.4. El Creador es inmaterial.

          4.2.4.1. Lo que sea material implica un cambio en los niveles atómico y molecular, pero el Creador no cambia. (4.2.3)

    4.2.5. El Creador es atemporal.

          4.2.5.1. En ausencia total de cambio, el tiempo no existe, y el Creador no cambia. (4.2.3)

    4.2.6. El Creador es inespacial.

          4.2.6.1. Lo que sea inmaterial y atemporal no puede ser espacial, y el Creador es inmaterial y atemporal (4.2.4, 4.2.5)

    4.2.7. El Creador es enormemente poderoso.

          4.2.7.1. Él creó el universo de la nada. (3)

5. Por lo tanto, existe un Creador personal e incausado del universo, que sin la creación es imprincipiado, inmutable, inmaterial, atemporal, inespacial y enormemente poderoso.

Ahora veamos la siguiente objeción a la que he llamado Argumento de la Inmutabilidad Contra una Causa Personal (AICCP):

1.Si Dios es atemporal, entonces es inmutable.
2.Si Dios es inmutable, entonces Dios no puede actuar para traer el universo a la existencia.
3.Dios es un ser personal que sin la creación es atemporal (otorgado por el Kalam).
4.Dios es inmutable (de 1 y 3)
5.Por lo tanto, Dios no puede actuar para traer el universo a la existencia (de 2 y 4).

Como pueden ver, el argumento ataca las premisas (4.1.3), (4.2.3) y (4.2.5) de nuestra versión del Kalam al intentar demostrar que existe una incoherencia entre las propiedades de Dios de ser personal, inmutable y atemporal.

¿Qué tan sólido es el argumento? Pues no mucho. Primero, el detractor parece pensar que, dado que no hay tiempo sin el universo, Dios es inmutable, pero este no es el caso. Lo que al argumento realmente dice, es lo siguiente:

(a) En ausencia total de cambio, el tiempo no existe y el Creador no cambia. (4.2.5.1.)

(b) Por lo tanto, Dios es atemporal (4.2.5.)

Y

(c) No puede existir una regresión temporal infinita de cambios. (4.2.3.1)

(d) Por lo tanto, Dios es inmutable (4.2.3)

Observa que el argumento no dice que la inmutabilidad de Dios se infiere de su atemporalidad; sino que la inmutabilidad se infiere de la imposibilidad de una regresión infinita de cambios, y la atemporalidad se infiere de su inmutabilidad. ¿Pero qué queremos decir por “ausencia de todo cambio”? Simple, es no hacer algo diferente. Es claro que hay actividades que no requieren ni cambio ni tiempo, por ejemplo, tener conocimiento de algo (Dios puede conocer todas las verdades en ese estado inmutable sin tiempo). Y lo mismo podrías decir sobre nuestras intenciones: mientras estas no cambien, podemos sostenerlas atemporalmente. Por lo que podemos decir que (1) del AICCP es falsa.

Segundo, (2) es falsa también. La premisa parece afirmar que la inmutabilidad de Dios es equivalente a inmovilidad, lo cuál sería cierto si habláramos de una causa impersonal, pero hemos visto que podemos inferir que la causa es personal, por lo que tiene volición para simplemente decidir crear el universo desde la eternidad. Tal como William Lane Craig explica cuando utiliza el ejemplo de un hombre sentado desde la eternidad:

[…] mi experimento mental sirve para ilustrar un punto sobre el libre albedrío. Una persona puede existir inmutable y entonces libremente ejecuta una cierta intención porque el libre albedrío no requiere alguna condición antecedente determinante. La misma naturaleza del libre albedrío es la ausencia de determinantes causales. Así que una acción libre tiene la apariencia de un evento puramente espontáneo. El hombre puede simple y libremente desear levantarse. Por lo que puedes obtener un efecto atemporal de una causa inmutable, si esa causa es un agente libre. Ahora, en el caso de Dios, Dios existe inmutablemente sin el universo. La creación es un acto del libre albedrío que, cuando ocurre, trae el tiempo a la existencia junto con el universo. Por lo tanto, decir que “desde un tiempo finito un Creador dotado de libre albedrío podría haber querido traer el mundo a la existencia en ese momento” no implica que había tiempo previo a ese momento.[1]

Ahora, en este punto existe la objeción de que entonces el tiempo no comienza con el inicio del universo, sino en el momento en que Dios decide traer el universo a la existencia, lo cual es contradictorio que las implicaciones del inicio del universo del Big Bang. Ahora, incluso cuando el Dr. Craig no sostiene que Dios tenga que deliberar temporalmente, él ha respondido a objeciones similares haciendo distinción entre el tiempo físico y el tiempo metafísico:

El tiempo metafísico es independiente de los procesos físicos, por ejemplo, si Dios estuviera haciendo una cuenta regresiva, él podría decir: “3, 2, 1, ¡que se haga la luz!” Y en este caso tendríamos una secuencia de eventos mentales, tendríamos tiempo previo al comienzo del universo. Lo que iniciaría al comienzo del universo sería el tiempo físico, el tiempo que es objeto de estudio en el campo de la física.[2]

Así que, con todo esto, podemos decir que el AICCP no es un argumento sólido después de todo.

Ahora pasemos al siguiente argumento al que he llamado Argumento de la Atemporalidad Contra la Causación (AACC):

1.Causa y efecto requieren intervalos temporales respectivamente para que pueda darse dicha relación.
2.El estado en el que se encuentra Dios no existen los intervalos temporales (otorgado por el kalam).
3.Por lo tanto, en el estado en el que se encuentra Dios no puede darse la causa ni el efecto.

Cuando uno analiza este argumento, notará que en esencia es similar al primero, solo se omite la inmutabilidad, pero el factor de atemporalidad sigue ahí, en específico, que se requiere de intervalos de tiempo para que exista una causa y efecto del tipo Dios tomando la decisión de crear el universo y luego otro momento en el que el universo llega a existir. Para esto William Lane Craig ha respondido en otra ocasión que:

[…]me parece que esta suposición es falsa. Porque en virtud de su omnisciencia, las elecciones de Dios no son eventos, ya que Él no delibera temporalmente ni Su voluntad se mueve de un estado de indecisión a uno de decisión. Simplemente tiene determinaciones libres de la voluntad para ejecutar ciertas acciones, y cualquier deliberación solo puede decirse que es explicativa, no temporalmente, antes de sus decretos.[3]

Regresemos ahora al asunto de que la causa debe preceder al efecto. Aunque el Dr. Craig ya abordando antes de que no existe ninguna razón para aceptar esa condición y de que es posible tener causa y efecto simultáneamente[4], también existe la posibilidad de que, de hecho, toda causa y efecto es en última instancia, simultaneo:

No veo ninguna incoherencia conceptual al pensar que una causa y su efecto pueden ser simultáneos. De hecho, los filósofos a menudo hablarán sobre cómo se percibe la dirección de la influencia causal entre A y B cuando A y B son simultáneos. A y B pueden ser al mismo tiempo, pueden ser simultáneos, pero ¿de qué manera trazas la línea de influencia causal? ¿Es A lo que está causando B, o B lo que está causando A? Los filósofos discutirán sobre eso. Así que no veo ninguna incoherencia en la noción de causación simultánea. De hecho, algunos metafísicos han argumentado que todas las causas son en última instancia simultáneas porque hasta que la causa realmente incida en algún otro objeto para producir un efecto, no hay forma de que la influencia causal pueda saltar a través del tiempo, desde t2 hasta t1, para producir el efecto en t1. Esa causa debe durar hasta el momento t1 y luego producir su efecto en ese momento. Pero no hay forma de que una influencia causal pueda viajar a través del tiempo y saltar de t2 a t1 para producir el evento. Así que muchos filósofos dirán que toda causación es, en última instancia, simultánea.

Creo que es un argumento muy persuasivo. No puedo ver cómo puedes tener influencia causal saltando en el tiempo. Me parece que el efecto no se producirá hasta que la causa realmente incida sobre la cosa para producir su efecto; por ejemplo, el taco debe golpear la bola de billar para ponerla en movimiento. Y hasta que no lo haga, no hay forma de que la influencia causal del movimiento del taco vaya a saltar en el tiempo para hacer que la bola se mueva.[5]

Conclusión

Hemos visto que el AICCP falla debido a un mal entendimiento del significado de inmutabilidad y de como se infiere la inmutabilidad. Por otro lado, aunque el AACC es un argumento mejor, no es del todo sólido; ya que no existen buenas razones para rechazar la simultaneidad de la causa y el efecto.

Notas

[1] William Lane Craig, “God and Time” en William Lane Craig: A Reasonable Response.

[2] An Explanation of Physical Time and Metaphysical Time.

[3] William Lane Craig, “Timelessness and Creation”.

[4] William Lane Craig, “Causation and Spacetime”.

[5] Misunderstandings About God and the Big Bang.

 


Jairo Izquierdo es parte del equipo de Social Media y autor para la organización cristiana Cross Examined.  Estudia filosofía y teología, siendo su actual foco de estudio la lógica clásica, epistemología, doctrinas cristianas y lingüística.  Es cofundador de Filósofo Cristiano. Es miembro en la Christian Apologetics Alliance y ministro de alabanza en la iglesia cristiana bautista Cristo es la Respuesta en Puebla, México.

By Maverick Christian

To begin, I will quote Alvin Plantinga:

The argument, in essence, is this: that we ordinarily think that the content of a belief, or an intention, or an action is relevant to the actions caused by beliefs, intentions, and actions. I believe that there is a beer in the fridge; we ordinarily think that it is in virtue of its content that this belief causes me to go to the fridge. I intend to get a beer from the fridge and I intend to do so; we ordinarily think that the content of this intention and of carrying it out is causally relevant to my action of going to the fridge. We don’t just ordinarily think these things; they are nothing but sobering truth. I’m going to argue that if materialism about us human beings… were true, then these things are false: It would not be in virtue of their content that beliefs, intentions, and actions do what they do. [1]

For simplicity, let’s just consider beliefs. In materialism, the belief coin has two sides: the neurophysiological/NF properties (certain neurons wire in a certain way, etc.) of the belief, and the actual semantic content of the belief (e.g., there’s a beer in the fridge ). In dualism (the idea that our minds are a composite of the physical brain and a nonphysical mental component, e.g., the soul) it is possible that the content of a belief can modify behavior; e.g., I believe something and on the basis of this belief my soul impacts my neural pathways in a certain way to cause a behavior.

On materialism, however, the content of a belief is causally irrelevant in the sense that (given materialism) a belief causes an effect in virtue of its NF properties, and not in virtue of its content. We can see this by doing a little thought experiment. Suppose a given person’s belief, say, the belief that there is a cold soda in the fridge , had the same NF properties, but a completely different content, such as that the moon is made of green cheese . Would the person’s behavior be different if the belief had the same NF properties, but different content? It wouldn’t, because having the same neurophysiological properties means that we would have the same electrical impulses traveling along the same neural pathways and thus emitting the same muscular contractions. So if materialism were true, the content of our beliefs would be causally irrelevant. The argument in a nutshell is this:

  1. If materialism is true, then the content of our beliefs is causally irrelevant.
  2. But the content of our beliefs is causally relevant.
  3. Therefore, materialism is false.

In response one might say that there is something wrong with the thought experiment, since it is metaphysically impossible for a given set of neurophysiological properties to have distinct semantic content. Even if I were a materialist, this does not seem at all plausible to me. The idea of ​​moving subatomic particles around producing semantic content seems almost mystical, and it seems easily conceivable that there is a possible world in which the same moving subatomic particles generate different semantic content, although as a materialist I would like to believe that this might involve the fine-tuning of some kind of physical necessity that makes the moving subatomic particles generate mental states. Still, to my mind’s eye such an adjustment seems conceivable and metaphysically possible.

But even if it is not possible for a given set of NF properties to have a different semantic content associated with it, does this prevent the statement “If a given set of NF properties were to have a different content, the behavior would be the same” from being meaningfully true? I think not. In philosophy, propositions of the form “If P were true, then Q would be true,” where P is an impossibility, are called counterpossible. There seem to be counterpossible statements that are meaningfully true. For example, suppose the renowned mathematician Kurt Gödel proved a certain theorem; it is impossible for theorems to turn out to be false, since they are necessarily true. However, as Alvin Plantinga points out, “If Mic were to prove that Gödel was wrong, mathematicians everywhere would be astonished; it is not true that if Mic were to prove that Gödel was wrong, mathematicians everywhere would yawn with boredom.” [2] So even if “if a given set of NF properties were to have a different content, it would result in the same behavior” were contra-possible, this does not seem to prevent the statement from being meaningfully true.

Reductive and non-reductionist materialism

Another way to try to avoid the semantic content of a belief being causally irrelevant is to take the view that a belief is just a combination of physical properties; the view that beliefs are reducible to physical states in this sort of way is called reductive materialism . Suppose we have P1, P2, P3… Pn to represent various physical properties (e.g., human neurophysiological properties), and let ∨ represent “or.” A reductive materialist might believe that a certain belief is just the disjunction (a set of things related by “or”) of certain physical properties like these:

P1∨ P2 ∨ P3…

Most likely, on reductive materialism a belief would be (merely) a disjunction of a set of physical properties that constitute a given mental state, something like this where & represents “and”:

(P1& P7 & P11…) ∨ (P5 & P63 &…) ∨…

The “∨” is necessary, since it is possible for different sets of physical states to correspond to a given belief (if materialism is true, for example, it would seem that alien neurophysiologies or mechanical silicon brains could also be configured to have a given belief). The above sort of structure “(A & B) ∨ (C & D & E) ∨…” is what logic and math gurus call a boolean combination . In contrast to reductionist materialism which says that beliefs are reducible to NF properties in the way described above, non-reductionist materialism denies this, but does make the claim that beliefs are determined by physical states. One might believe that a belief emerges from physical properties in a way that is roughly analogous to moisture emerging from the combination of hydrogen and oxygen in H2O.

A reductionist materialist might claim that since beliefs are just a (Boolean) combination of NF properties, it might well be that it is in virtue of having semantic content that a belief is causally relevant (this is not necessarily so, because belief is really a disjunction of sets of NF properties, so it would still be possible for a person’s belief to produce behavior in virtue of its NF properties rather than its semantic content, but a reductionist materialist might believe that it is at least possible for a human being’s belief to produce behavior in virtue of having content).

The problem with reductive materialism

Plantinga argues that even if it is true that a belief is causally relevant in virtue of its having a certain content, it does not follow that the semantic content is itself causally relevant. Plantinga gives the following illustration. Suppose Alvin throws a ball that has a mass of 0.2 kilograms, and the ball hits a glass window, causing it to break. If the ball had been much lighter (say, the mass of a feather), it would not have broken the glass, so the ball breaks the window in virtue of (among other things) its being 0.2 kilograms. Now suppose that the property of having a mass of 0.2 kg is Sam’s favorite property. Thus, we have the following:

Having a mass of 0.2 kg = Sam’s favorite property

Since having a mass of 0.2 kg is Sam’s favorite property (which is not his favorite property by definition, but reductionist materialists similarly do not [normally] believe that the identity relation between a belief and a boolean combination of NF properties holds by definition), then it follows that a ball breaks the window in virtue of having Sam’s favorite property. And yet:

Having a mass of 0.2 kg is Sam’s favorite property.

It doesn’t actually seem to have anything to do with the ball breaking the window, even though it is in virtue of having Sam’s favorite property of the ball breaking the window. Similarly, the fact that a set of NF properties is a belief doesn’t seem to have anything to do with the set of NF properties causing behavior, even though it is true that a belief causes behavior in virtue of having a certain semantic content.

I think we can make this clearer by considering the following thought experiment. Suppose that reductionist materialism is true and a mad scientist inserts a belief interface device (BID) into Smith’s brain, which acts as a new interface between Smith’s belief and behavior. For example, the mad scientist sets up the BID so that when Smith believes that I am thirsty, the NF properties of this belief electrochemically affect the BID and the BID subsequently causes Smith’s body to take a drink of water. The mad scientist can set up the BID at will so that any given belief can cause almost any behavior. For example, the mad scientist sets up the BID so that the NF properties of the belief that drinking water will kill me and I don’t want to die trigger an electrochemical reaction that (thanks to the belief interface device) causes Smith’s body to get a drink of water. The mad scientist sets up the CID again so that the NF properties of the belief that I will never see a Nicolas Cage movie cause Smith to go see a Nicolas Cage movie, and the NF properties of the belief that grass is air cause Smith to eat coconut ice cream after a fish dinner. All of this would be possible on reductionist materialism because a human being’s belief causes effects in virtue of its NF properties, not its semantic content, even if it were the case that beliefs are just (boolean) combinations of NF properties.

The DIC scenario shows that it is the NF properties of a belief and how those properties interact with the rest of the physical system that determines our behavior. DIC may be science fiction, but even in our own naturally occurring belief interface system, it is the NF properties of a belief and how those properties interact with the rest of our physiology that determines our behavior. To look at this slightly differently, let PS1, PS2, PS3… PSn each be a set of physical properties, e.g. PS1 is short for (P1 & P7 & P11…). Now suppose that the semantic content of the belief that I am thirsty is just a boolean combination of the physical properties like this:

PS1∨ PS2 ∨ PS3 ∨… ∨ PSn

Now imagine that Smith’s belief that I am thirsty is PS1. Plantinga would say that Smith’s belief does things in virtue of its physical (in this case, neurophysiological) properties rather than in virtue of the physical properties of being part of the Boolean combination that I am thirsty—just as when the ball breaks the window, in virtue of having a mass of 0.2 kilograms rather than in virtue of having a mass of 0.2 kg being Sam’s favorite property.

We can see that this is the case with any other thought experiment. Modifying Smith’s physiology a little, holding the NF properties of the belief (PS1) constant, and the NF properties of Smith’s belief that I am thirsty could cause something quite different, e.g. the physical properties of PS1 triggering an electrochemical reaction causing Smith to ignore the water around him and have to eat sand instead. This would be physically possible, since it is the NF properties of a belief and how those properties interact with the rest of the physical system that determine our behavior. Given materialism, it would just be a matter of luck (e.g. favorable physical laws) that belief and behavior are linked in a “rational” way by mimicking the semantic content influencing behavior, e.g. the NF properties of the belief that this plant is poisonous and hence I will not eat it causes me not to eat the plant, unlike the NF properties of the belief that grass is air causes me not to eat the plant. In any case, the thought experiment does illustrate that it is the NF properties of the belief and how those properties interact with the rest of the physical system that determine our behavior. Just as having a mass of 0.2 kg being Sam’s favorite property doesn’t seem to have anything to do with why the ball breaks the window, so too does PS1 being a member of the Boolean combination of I’m thirsty not seem to have anything to do with why PS1 does the things it does. If that is true, then the semantic content of a belief seems to be causally irrelevant in the sense that a belief does things in virtue of its NF properties, and not because of its semantic content.

Conclusion

Given materialism, the semantic content of a belief is causally irrelevant in the sense that a belief does things in virtue of its NF properties, not because of its semantic content. If a given set of NF properties had different semantic content, it would result in the same behavior (the same neurophysiological properties means we would have the same electrical impulses traveling along the same neural pathways and thus emitting the same muscle contractions). Even if reductionist materialism were true, beliefs seem to cause behavior in virtue of their NF properties, not because of their semantic content. The DIC scenario in particular illustrates that even on reductionist materialism, the semantic content of a belief can be absolutely unrelated to the person’s external environment when that belief causes behavior, for example, the situation in which the NF properties of the belief that grass is air cause Smith to eat coconut ice cream. So we have the following argument:

  1. If materialism is true, then the content of our beliefs is causally irrelevant.
  2. But the content of our beliefs is causally relevant.
  3. Therefore, materialism is false.

If materialism were true, a belief would do things in virtue of its NF properties and how those properties interact with the rest of the physical system. Even if the semantic content of a belief is just a boolean combination of physical properties, a set of physical properties that is a member of that boolean combination seems to have nothing to do with why that set of physical properties causally affects other things in one’s body, just as having a mass of 0.2 kg being Sam’s favorite property seems to have nothing to do with why the ball breaks the window.

Grades

[1] Plantinga, Alvin. “A New Argument against Materialism”  Philosophia Christi  14.1 (Summer 2012) p. 9

[2] Plantinga, Alvin. “A New Argument against Materialism”  Philosophia Christi  14.1 (Summer 2012) p. 21

 


Original Blog: http://bit.ly/2ZVw4bT

Translated and edited by Jairo Izquierdo

By Carlos E. Rodriguez

In their arguments for the existence of a being that transcends the universe, Christian theists often identify this being with the name of God. What we are going to do is to provide a clear and simple meaning of this concept.

How do we define God?

This word can be used as a common noun or a proper noun. In my case, and in the case of many, I use it as a proper noun. It contains the concept of a being that possesses characteristic properties. There are two ways to know what properties this concept possesses: one comes through the theology revealed in the Bible, and another comes through Anselm’s theology of the perfect being . These two are not mutually exclusive, but rather use different paths to reach the same point.

We say that God is a proper name that is attributed to a being that possesses properties. From the theology of perfect being, we say that these properties are maximally great. In this way, when we speak of God, in Anselm’s terms, we speak of the maximally great being that can be conceived. If you can conceive of a being greater than him, you are conceiving of God. From this point of view, a maximally great being possesses maximal properties, such as Omnipotence, Omniscience, etc.

With all this in mind, we say that God is a personal being, worthy of worship, immaterial, timeless without the universe, a-spatial, perfectly free, eternal, Omnipotent, Omniscient, Omnipresent, the locus of goodness, creator of all things, etc. Instead of mentioning each property that the being that receives this name possesses, we summarize it (preferably) with the Anselmian statement: “the greatest being that exists.” Such a being possesses all the maximum properties and qualities that can be conceived.

In this way, we have a concept of what is meant by God.

Jehovah, the God mentioned in the Bible, is God

Why is Jehovah treated as God? Because the attributes or properties that he possesses are the same as those of a supremely great being. If we go to the Bible, and use a method that uses revealed theology as a source, we find that Jehovah is:

  1. Immaterial, for He is spirit. John 4:24, “God is spirit, and those who worship Him must worship in spirit and truth,” is also implied in several references to His invisibility (John 1:18; 1 Timothy 1:17; 6:15-16).
  2. Omniscient, for “he knows all things” (1 John 3:20).
  3. Necessary and self-existent (Isaiah 40:17-23; Revelation 4:11).
  4. Eternal (Psalms 90:1-4; 102:11-12, 25-27).
  5. Omnipresent (Psalms 139:7-12).
  6. Omnipotent (Genesis 17:1; Revelation 19:6).
  7. Holy (Leviticus 19:2).
  8. Love (1 John 4:7-21).

If Jehovah possesses the properties of a supremely great being, and this being is called God, then Jehovah is God. It is the attributes and properties, referred to in the Bible but also deducible through natural theology, that give Jehovah the right to be called God.

 


Carlos Enrique Rodríguez Alcántara is from the Dominican Republic, a blogger, preacher, teacher, speaker, and apologist. Husband of Carolina. Member of the Central Rock of Salvation Church, where he has been director of education and deputy director of education for the council. He has an associate degree in theology from ESFOTEBIC. He holds a certificate in philosophy, philosophy and science (with honors) and critical thinking from the University of Edinburgh, as well as philosophy, science, and religion from the same university.

Original Blog: http://bit.ly/2R8qdfS