Español

Since this philosophical movement has become very popular these days on social media, I have found it necessary to write this note to explain what postmodernism really is; since I often notice that many people use the adjective “postmo” as a synonym for “progressive” or “chairo”, when they are not (although I do not mean to say that they are exclusive), or that being postmodern is unique to atheism, which is totally false.

Addressing the topic of postmodernism would require more than a few simple pages, so this writing will be to clarify in a simple and brief way what postmodernism represents in a very general way.

First, postmodernism covers not only the philosophical movement that followed modernism, but also cultural, artistic and literary movements. So keep in mind that the whole thing on social media is about philosophical ideology; so as not to think that when someone criticizes a “postmo” they are referring to some artist or literary person (although this may well be the case, but usually it is the philosopher).

Second, postmodernism covers a multitude of theses (or antitheses, depending on the case), so always keep in mind that one postmodern is not identical to another postmodern, nor does one hold each and every one of the positions we will see below, so it is important that when you come across a postmodern you first ask why he holds that position, what his specific points of view are.

Third. In general, postmodernism, as a philosophical movement, is above all an epistemic reinterpretation; that is, of what knowledge is and what counts as knowledge. Postmodernism goes beyond the issue of gender ideology, which is the most well-known topic of debate, but rather a cultural relativism about reality, truth, reason, value, linguistic meaning, logic, sameness, among other notions. The main exponents of postmodernism; the best known are Friedrich Nietzsche, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Jacques Derrida, Martin Heidegger, among others.

That said, let’s look at the most common philosophical positions held by postmodernism.

Metaphysical anti-realism. Postmodernism rejects the existence of language-independent reality, the reality of the external world, and the application of the laws of logic to reality. In other words you already know, “it’s a social construct,” the old reliable of postmodernism.

Rejection of theories of truth. “There is no such thing as objective truth.” “There are no absolute truths.” You’ve heard that, right? Well, that’s also postmodern. The reason? “It’s a social construct.”

Epistemic subjectivity: Since for postmodernists knowledge is a social construction and not an objective and justified representation of the reality of our mental states, it follows that there is no position from which knowledge itself can be defined without resorting to begging the question.

Anti-essentialism. Essentialism, in simple terms, is the position that some entities have both essential and accidental properties. An essential property is one that if the object were to cease to possess, it would cease to be what it is. For example, being an animal is a property of a cow. Accidental properties are ones that if the object in question were to cease to possess them, it would still be what it is. For example, the dog Snoopy has the accidental property of having white fur and black ears. If Snoopy were entirely brown instead of white with black ears, Snoopy would still be a dog. According to postmodernists, there is no objective distinction between essential and accidental properties, but rather they are relative to our own criteria of classification. At this point you will have noticed those who currently reject essentialism: the gender ideologues. For example, since there is no objective difference between the essential properties that make a man a man and a woman a woman, gender ideologists use this to impose their ideology that any person can be whatever they want.

Subjective meaning of language and thought. First, postmodernists reject the idea that language objects have authorial meaning, depriving the author of interpreting his own work. Second, they claim that thought cannot exist without language and that thought is nothing more than linguistic behavior relative to social groups.

Anti-metanarratives. A metanarrative is either a procedure for determining which conceptual scheme/worldview is true/rational or a reference to worldviews that have come to be accepted by large groups of people, such as atheism or Christianity, among others. By stating that there are no metanarratives, it follows that there is no way to decide which worldview is true or that any worldview is true.

There are other positions that are held by postmodernists, but those mentioned in this note are the most common and the most mentioned in the current social controversy. Therefore, it must be taken into account that although one can make fun of postmodern positions, these are reinterpretations of very deep philosophical positions that are topics of serious study for disciplines such as epistemology, axiology, metaphysics, philosophy of language, etc. Therefore, I invite the reader to dedicate time to study some article on these topics in question.

I also want to point out that postmodernism is not an ideology exclusive to atheism. There are currently theistic philosophers who share one or more of these postmodern positions with certain variations given their commitment to theism. For example, the Christian philosopher Alfonso Ropero maintains that there are no absolute truths, and that if they did exist, they could only be known by God.

Much more could be said about postmodernism, so I will leave a few resources at the end of the note so that the interested reader can delve deeper into the subject in question.

References

“Theories of Truth and Postmodernism” by JP Moreland and WL Craig in Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview .

“Modernism and Postmodernism”. See:   http://www.monografias.com/trabajos/modypostmod/modypostmod.shtml (Accessed 30/Dec/2016).

“Do We Live in a Postmodern Society?” See:  http://www.reasonablefaith.org/spanish/vivimos-en-una-sociedad-postmoderna (Accessed 30/Dec/2016).

“Sexuality and Gender: Conclusions from Biology, Psychology and the Social Sciences” See: http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/preface (Accessed 12/30/2016).

 

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek 

 


Jairo Izquierdo is a member of the Social Media team and an author for the Christian organization Cross Examined . He studies philosophy and theology, with his current focus being classical logic, epistemology, Christian doctrines, and philosophy of language. He is co-founder of Filósofo Cristiano . He is a member of the Christian Apologetics Alliance and a worship director at the Christian Baptist church Cristo es la Respuesta in Puebla, Mexico.

Por Shadow To Light

Uno de los argumentos centrales del movimiento del Nuevo Ateismo insiste en que la ciencia y la religión son «incompatibles”. Los científicos no deben ser religiosos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, se supone que deben abandonar su religión. El argumento es convincente solo para nuevos ateos, simplemente porque es más un tema de conversación para su propaganda anti-religiosa que cualquier tipo de argumento sólido. De hecho, podemos decir que es solo un tema de conversación debido a la naturaleza injustificada selectiva de la comparación. Es decir, si la ciencia es incompatible con la religión, ¿no podría ser también incompatible con otras formas de expresión humana?

Jerry Coyne recientemente escribió un post racionalizando su uso de ad hominems  y el lenguaje inflamatorio:

¿Sabes qué? Me importa un pepino el tono de las declaraciones. Esto es exactamente lo que es de esperar en los sitios web (no en revistas académicas, nota), en un caso que no es puramente académico, sino político. [….] las invectivas del DI me resbalan por la espalda. Hubo un tiempo en ellos -yo creo que fue William Dembski-, que publicaron una foto de mí junto a una de Herman Munster, señalando el parecido.

Con el tiempo la quitaron, pero no me molestó en absoluto. La sátira es una de las armas en esta batalla entre la racionalidad y la superstición.

Claro. En política, la invectiva y la sátira tienen un lugar. En lo político, se busca cambiar la opinión y el comportamiento con el uso de invectivas, la sátira, y otras formas de propaganda. Pero aquí está la cosa.

Este enfoque es incompatible con el enfoque científico. En la ciencia, podemos cambiar opiniones con los resultados experimentales. Cambiamos de opinión con la evidencia científica. Al tratar de comprender cómo la comunidad científica llegó a aceptar la idea de que el ADN era el material genético, sólo tenemos que tener en cuenta algunos de los famosos experimentos que demostraron esto. La invectiva y la sátira no jugaron un papel.

El mismo Coyne reconoce la diferencia cuando escribe: “Esto es exactamente lo que es de esperar en los sitios web (no en revistas académicas, nota), en un caso que no es puramente académico, sino político”.

Sitios web, revistas no académicas.

No es puramente académico, sino político.

En otras palabras, la ciencia y la política son incompatibles. En las ciencias cambiamos opiniones con los resultados experimentales y en la política cambiamos opiniones con la invectiva y la sátira. La ciencia cambia de opinión, apelando a la razón, Mientras la política cambia de opiniones mediante la manipulación de las emociones.

Ahora, recordemos que los nuevos ateos argumentan que los científicos no deben ser religiosos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, se supone que abandonará su religión. La misma lógica también significaría que los científicos no se suponga que sean políticos y si alguien realmente valora la ciencia, deben abandonar toda postura y actividad política. Los científicos, y todos los que valoran la ciencia, deben ser completamente apolíticos. 

Por supuesto, El Nuevo Ateísmo, por su propia naturaleza, es político. Lo que significa que El Nuevo ateísmo es incompatible con la ciencia.  Los Nuevos Ateos nunca lo admitirían, dado que su movimiento es puramente político y no tiene ningún compromiso con la razón.

 


Traducido por Jorge Gil Calderón

Blog Original: https://bit.ly/2Y1Aq3s

Por Carlos E. Rodríguez

En la primera entrega de esta serie de posts establecimos en qué consiste la acusación y/o pregunta, muchas veces de forma sincera, acerca de nuestra confianza al texto bíblico y su fidelidad en transmitir, a través de los años, realmente lo que se escribió al inicio. Para ello hablamos de forma general de algunos casos en donde si cambiar el texto hubiese sido una tendencia general, no tendríamos razón para encontrar pasajes que sirven más como municiones para los críticos que para apoyar las afirmaciones de la creencia cristiana. También, se presentó un sencillo argumento que dice lo siguiente:

  1. Si la Biblia ha sido cambiada entonces la Biblia no puede contener errores.
  2. La Biblia contiene errores.
  3. Por lo tanto, la Biblia no ha sido cambiada.

 Lo más sobresaliente en este silogismo, que usa el modus tolens en su inferencia, es que depende de la condición de que la Biblia contiene errores. Los críticos dicen que sí. Así que usando sus propios casos para validar esta premisa hemos concluido que contiene “errores” y que no ha sido cambiada. No podemos tener las 2 cosas: o contiene errores o ha sido cambiada, pero no ambas a la vez. Como esta serie no trata de corregir o argumentar para explicar los casos de errores en el texto, comenzamos con buen pie en nuestro camino de responder con un no a la pregunta de si el texto bíblico ha sido cambiado. Y la mejor prueba en la línea de evidencia consiste justamente en dar por válida la creencia generalizada entre los críticos del cristianismo.

Lo que haré en esta ocasión es darle un poco más de fuerza a la idea de que el texto no ha sido cambiado viendo pasajes en él que son de dificultad para algunas creencias doctrinales dentro del cristianismo. También mencionaré algunos pasajes vergonzosos que afectan en cierto modo la imagen del mensaje cristiano.

Pasajes con dificultad

Imaginemos por un momento que sí, la práctica de cambiar el texto era habitual o hasta escasa, para ayudar a la idea; y se hacía cuando era necesario corregir un texto, pasaje o libro que entraba en conflicto con las creencias en el momento o con el desarrollo de las mismas a través de los años. Si esto pasó en la antigüedad, no deberíamos encontrar esos pasajes. Pero que creen: los seguimos encontrado. Es más, tenemos evidencia de que están en el texto desde hace siglos, pues la mayoría, sino todos, aparecen en las copias más antiguas de los textos bíblicos que poseemos hoy. Y siguiendo la lógica de la crítica, no debería ser esto posible. Aquí puede surgir una nueva acusación para evitar caer en este absurdo que destruiría la misma acusación en base a lo que ella dice. Alguien puede decir que el cambio a esos pasajes se hizo, pero en los textos que hoy no tenemos o no hemos encontrado aún, y el resultado de ellos es el texto que sí tenemos desde las copias más antiguas. Sí, esto puede ser una posibilidad, pero el punto es: ¿Qué evidencia respalda esta suposición? Ninguna. Así que nunca algo posible va a tener más validez que lo que sí tiene evidencia. En este caso: los mismos pasajes que presentan una dificultad a las doctrinas cristianas están ahí desde las copias más antiguas de los manuscritos que tenemos, y esto es evidencia clara de que por lo menos desde ese punto en adelante, no ha habido cambios en el texto. ¿Cuáles son esos textos que presentan una dificultad a las creencias cristianas y que si la tendencia ha sido cambiar la biblia a nuestro antojo no deberían esta?

Mateo 24:36

Pero del día y la hora nadie sabe, ni aun los ángeles de los cielos, sino sólo mi Padre.

En el cuerpo de doctrina del cristianismo ortodoxo se afirma que Cristo es Dios, y que posee todos los atributos de Dios, como la Omnisciencia. Aquí tenemos a Cristo afirmando no saber algo. Esto supone un problema para la enseñanza de esta doctrina, pues está contenida en los evangelios mismos, los cuales son la fuente más segura para saber de Jesús y lo que dijo, y aquí tenemos que él dice que hay algo que no sabe. En vez de buscar alguna explicación para esto, si la tendencia de la iglesia era de cambiar el texto, es más fácil eliminar esto o cambiarlo, que dejarlo como una dificultad que estaría ahí a través de los siglos, pues déjeme informarle que justamente este pasaje es usado para decir que Jesús no puede ser Dios, pues aquí lo tenemos afirmando algo que lo demuestra.

Job 2:3

Y Jehová dijo a Satanás: ¿No has considerado a mi siervo Job, que no hay otro como él en la tierra, varón perfecto y recto, temeroso de Dios y apartado del mal, y que todavía retiene su integridad, aun cuando tú me incitaste contra él para que lo arruinara sin causa?

Dentro de las creencias centrales del cristianismo está la que dice que Dios no puede ser tentado por el mal ni caer en él, pero aquí tenemos un texto que nos dice que él sí cayó en hacer el mal. No tengo ni que recordar lo mismo que dije anteriormente, pues era más fácil cambiar este pasaje que dejarlo ahí por los siglos para que sea usado en contra de dicha creencia. Pero, aún está ahí, demostrando que el texto no ha sufrido esos cambios que proponen los críticos.

Los pasajes que representan una dificultad para explicar las doctrinas cristianas, su mera existencia textual en la Biblia, es prueba de que esta no ha sido cambiada en la forma de la que se acusa.

Pasajes vergonzosos

Este tipo de texto no debería de existir en una escritura que ha sido vilmente manipulada al antojo. Sin embargo, ahí están. Al igual que con los que presentan una dificultad, estos prueban que no han ocurrido tales cambios propuestos por la crítica.

Algunos pasajes vergonzosos son:

Mateo 3:15-16

Pero Jesús le respondió: Deja ahora, porque así conviene que cumplamos toda justicia. Entonces le dejó. Y Jesús, después que fue bautizado, subió luego del agua; y he aquí los cielos le fueron abiertos, y vio al Espíritu de Dios que descendía como paloma, y venía sobre él.

Esta escena es vergonzosa por el hecho de que el enviado de Dios, Jesús, el cordero sin mancha, tiene que participar de un ritual que consiste en arrepentirse de los pecados. Pero si él es sin pecado, por qué debe arrepentirse de los mismos. Esto demostraría que él no fue tan integro como se supone. Recuerde que estoy hablando lo que la crítica dice, y razonando dentro de sus propias ideas.

Si esta escena está en el texto y no se ha quitado o cambiado, es porque esta práctica no era usada.

Juan 7:3-4

Y le dijeron sus hermanos: Sal de aquí, y vete a Judea, para que también tus discípulos vean las obras que haces. Porque ninguno que procura darse a conocer hace algo en secreto. Si estas cosas haces, manifiéstate al mundo. 5Porque ni aun sus hermanos creían en él.

Esta escena nos muestra como el Cristo, el ungido de Dios, no era ni bien visto por sus hermanos. Ni aun ellos creían en él. Cuando ni tu propia familia lo hace, hay razones para poner en duda de que realmente seas lo que afirmas ser. ¿No se supone que los primeros en creer en él debieron ser sus familiares? Pero aquí vemos que no lo hacían. Esto es más que suficiente para presentar la idea de que él no era realmente el Cristo. Este pasaje vergonzoso sería una razón aun para afirmar que fueron sus discípulos que, posterior a su muerte, le atribuyeron dicho título. Con todo esto, volvemos a preguntar: ¿por qué no fue cambiado este pasaje? Tal vez se debe a que esa no era una práctica ni generalizada ni escasa, en la iglesia antigua.

La idea es simple: pasajes como estos y otros debieron ser eliminados o cambiados. Si no se hizo solo debe tener una explicación: nada se cambiaba en la manera de que se acusa. En este punto alguien puede sugerir, para salvar la idea, de que no se cambiaron porque ya eran bastantes conocidos. Ahora, esto es tan absurdo que supone 2 cosas:

  1. Que los antiguos eran tan tontos que cuando “inventaron” esta historia estaban tan afanados por darla a conocer que no leyeron lo que escribieron. Es decir, nadie lo leyó, solo se escribió y se lanzó.
  2. Que no se les pudo ocurrir usar la misma técnica de la que se les acusa que usaron a su favor en el pasado. Es decir, ellos podrían inventar otro manuscrito corregido, y decir que el que contiene los errores y fallos fue adulterado y/o cambiado tan deliberadamente que su fin era manchar la imagen del cristianismo y lo que este enseña. Digo, para un grupo que tenga tan común el cambio del texto bíblico a su favor, ¿por qué no lo usarían una vez más para salir de este problema?

Al final todo es obvio: los críticos han fallado en esto.

Conclusión

Con elementos que prueban directamente que la sola idea del cambio deliberado a su favor no es plausible, podemos rechazar la validez de la acusación. Ni siquiera entra en la categoría de sugerencia, pues usando las mismas afirmaciones de la crítica y razonando dentro de su propio círculo de ideas, vemos que no hay forma de justificar su caso.

Recursos recomendados en Español:

Robándole a Dios (tapa blanda), (Guía de estudio para el profesor) y (Guía de estudio del estudiante) por el Dr. Frank Turek

Por qué no tengo suficiente fe para ser un ateo (serie de DVD completa), (Manual de trabajo del profesor) y (Manual del estudiante) del Dr. Frank Turek 

 


Carlos Enrique Rodríguez Alcántara es de República Dominicana, bloguero, predicador, maestro, conferencista y apologista. Esposo de Carolina. Miembro de la Iglesia Roca de Salvación Central, en donde ha sido director de educación y sub-director de educación del concilio. Tiene un grado asociado en teología de ESFOTEBIC. Certificado en filosofía, filosofía y ciencias (con honores) y pensamiento crítico por la universidad de Edimburgo, además de filosofía, ciencia y religión por la misma universidad.

Por The Poached Egg

“Jesús es absolutamente único en la historia. En la enseñanza, en el ejemplo, en el carácter, una excepción, una maravilla, y Él mismo es la evidencia del cristianismo” A.T. Pierson

“Así que yo me quedo con Él, no con el que afirma ser sabio, Confucio; o el que afirmaba ser iluminado, Buda; o el que afirmaba ser un profeta, Mahoma; sino con el que afirmaba ser Dios en carne humana. El que declaró: “Antes que Abraham fuese, yo soy” – y lo demostró” Norman Geisler

“En el Antiguo Testamento tenemos a Jesús anunciado. En los Evangelios tenemos a Jesús revelado. En los Hechos tenemos a Jesús predicado. En las epístolas tenemos a Jesús explicado. En el Apocalipsis tenemos a Jesús esperado. En el Apocalipsis, tenemos a Jesús esperando” Desconocido

“Soy historiador, no soy creyente, pero debo confesar como historiador que este pobre predicador de Nazaret es irrevocablemente el centro de la historia. Jesucristo es sencillamente la figura más dominante de toda la historia” H.G. Wells 

“A medida que pasan los siglos, se acumulan las pruebas de que, medido por su efecto en la historia, Jesús es la vida más influyente jamás vivida en este planeta”  Kenneth Scott Latourette

“Sócrates enseñó durante 40 años, Platón durante 50, Aristóteles durante 40, y Jesús por tan solo 3. Sin embargo, la influencia del ministerio de 3 años de Cristo trasciende infinitamente el impacto dejado por los 130 años combinados de enseñanza de estos hombres que estuvieron entre los más grandes filósofos de toda la antigüedad” Anónimo

“Fue este mismo Jesús, el Cristo, quien, entre muchas otras cosas notables, dijo y repitió algo que, procediendo de cualquier otro individuo, lo habría condenado de inmediato como un fanfarrón ególatra o una persona peligrosamente desequilibrada. Cuando dijo que Él mismo resucitaría de entre los muertos, al tercer día después de ser crucificado, dijo algo que solo un tonto se atrevería a decir, si esperaba una mayor devoción de cualquier discípulo, a menos que estuviera seguro de que iba a resucitar. ¡Ningún fundador de ninguna religión del mundo conocido por los hombres se atrevió a decir algo así!” Wilbur Smith

“Muchos están dispuestos a que Cristo sea algo, pero pocos consentirán que Cristo sea todo” Alexander Moody Stuart

“La vida de Jesús fue una tormenta de controversias. Los apóstoles, como los profetas antes que ellos, difícilmente podían pasar un día sin controversia. Pablo dijo que debatió diariamente en el mercado. Evitar la controversia es evitar a Cristo. Podemos tener paz, pero es una paz servil y carnal donde la verdad es asesinada en las calles” R.C. Sproul 

“La evidencia de la vida, muerte y resurrección de nuestro Señor puede ser, y a menudo ha sido, demostrada como satisfactoria; es buena según las reglas comunes para distinguir la evidencia buena de la mala. Miles y decenas de miles de personas la han revisado pieza por pieza con el mismo cuidado con el que cada juez resume un caso importante. Yo mismo lo he hecho muchas veces, no para persuadir a otros sino para satisfacerme a mí mismo. He sido utilizado durante muchos años para estudiar las historias de otros tiempos y para examinar y sopesar la evidencia de aquellos que han escrito sobre ellas, y no conozco ningún hecho en la historia de la humanidad que esté probado por una mejor y más completa evidencia de todo tipo, para el entendimiento de un justo investigador, que la gran señal que Dios nos ha dado de que Cristo murió y resucitó de la muerte” Thomas Arnold

“El mundo moderno detesta la autoridad pero adora la relevancia. Nuestra convicción cristiana es que la Biblia tiene tanto autoridad como relevancia, y que el secreto de ambas es Jesucristo” John Stott 

“En una civilización como la nuestra, creo que todos deben aceptar las afirmaciones de Jesucristo sobre Su vida, o ser culpables de ignorar o evadir la realidad” C.S. Lewis

Recursos recomendados en Español:

Robándole a Dios (tapa blanda), (Guía de estudio para el profesor) y (Guía de estudio del estudiante) por el Dr. Frank Turek

Por qué no tengo suficiente fe para ser un ateo (serie de DVD completa), (Manual de trabajo del profesor) y (Manual del estudiante) del Dr. Frank Turek  

 


Blog Original: http://bit.ly/33gJMsw

Traducido por Jorge Gil

Editado por María Andreina Cerrada

Por Evan Minton

Los no Molinistas usualmente acusan a los Molinistas de leer filosofía sobre la Biblia. Ellos dicen que el Molinismo es una teoría filosófica que no se encuentra en las páginas de la Escritura, y esta es una de las razones por las cuales ellos rechazan el Molinismo como una perspectiva teológica viable. Pero creo que hay varias razones buenas para pensar que el Molinismo es verdadero. En este blog, expondré cinco razones por las cuales acepto la teoría de Luis de Molina.

1 Un Dios verdaderamente Omnisciente sabría contrafácticos

¿Es Dios omnisciente? La Biblia dice que lo es. La Biblia dice “Grande es el Señor nuestro, y de mucho poder; y su entendimiento es infinito” (Salmos 145:7), “Sus ojos están sobre los caminos del hombre, y ve todos sus pasos. No hay tinieblas ni sombra de muerte donde se escondan los que hacen maldad. No hay carga, pues él al hombre más de lo justo, para que vaya con Dios a juicio” (Job 34:21-23) y “Los ojos de Jehová están en todo lugar, mirando a los malos y a los buenos”. (Proverbios 15:3).

Después de que Jesús resucitó de los muertos, él cocinó peces para los discípulos. Jesús y Simón Pedro tuvieron la siguiente discusión: “Cuando hubieron comido, Jesús dijo a Simón Pedro, ‘Simón, hijo de Jonás, ¿me amas más que éstos?’ “Sí, Señor”, él dijo, “tú sabes que te amo’. Jesús dijo, ‘Alimenta a mis ovejas’, la tercera vez que él le dijo ‘Simón, hijo de Jonás, ¿me amas? ‘él dijo, ‘Señor, tú lo sabes todo; tú sabes que te amo”. (Juan 21:15-17). Pedro dijo que Jesús sabía “todas las cosas”, y Jesús no intentó corregirlo (lo que implica que él estaba de acuerdo con la declaración de Pedro). La Biblia afirma que Dios conoce todas las cosas.

Sin embargo, si Dios no posee conocimiento de los contrafácticos, entonces ¿cómo es que él es omnisciente? ¡Habría cosas que Dios no sabría! Dios no sabría qué hubiera sucedido si tú te hubieras salido ayer de tu casa un poco antes o un poco después. Dios no sabría cómo resultaría tu vida si hubieras rechazado la propuesta de matrimonio de tu esposo. Dios no sabe si tú te hubieras intoxicado si hubieras decidido comer en cierto restaurante en cierto día. ¿Cómo es que Dios puede ser un Ser Máximamente Grandioso su él es menos que omnisciente?

2 La Biblia Describe que Dios conoce los Contrafácticos.

Aquellos que son detractores del Molinismo usualmente argumentan contra el Molinismo diciendo que los contrafácticos no tienen valor de verdad (es decir, no pueden ser ni verdaderos ni falsos), así que decir que Dios no es omnisciente porque no conoce acerca de los contrafácticos es como decir que él no es omnipotente porque él no puede crear círculos cuadrados o rocas demasiado pesadas que él mismo no puede levantar.

Dios no puede hacer lo lógicamente imposible, pero no diríamos que él no es omnipotente debido a ello. En la misma forma, Dios no puede conocer lo lógicamente imposible, así que ¿por qué decir que él no es omnisciente a causa de ello? Olvidemos que la posibilidad lógica de conocer los contrafácticos parece intuitiva (basamos nuestros juicios diarios todo el tiempo en lo que pensamos que son contrafácticos verdaderos), el problema más grande con estos negadores del conocimiento medio es que la Biblia presenta diversas ocasiones en las cuales Dios afirma el conocimiento de contrafácticos. Una pequeña muestra de versos se provee a continuación:

[Jesús está hablando aquí]  “¡Ay de ti, Corazín! ¡Ay de ti, Betsaida! Porque si en Tiro y en Sidón se hubieran hecho los milagros que han sido hechos en vosotras, tiempo ha que se hubieran arrepentido en cilicio y en ceniza. Por tanto os digo que en el día del juicio, será más tolerable el castigo para Tiro y para Sidón, que para vosotras. Y tú, Capernaum, que eres levantada hasta el cielo, hasta el Hades serás abatida; porque si en Sodoma se hubieran hecho los milagros que han sido hechos en ti, habría permanecido hasta el día de hoy”.

Mateo 11:21 – 23

Más hablamos sabiduría de Dios en misterio, la sabiduría oculta, la cual Dios predestinó antes de los siglos para nuestra gloria, la que ninguno de los príncipes de este siglo conoció; porque si la hubieran conocido, nunca habrían crucificado al Señor de gloria”.

1 Corintios 2:7 – 8

¿Me entregarán los vecinos de Keila en sus manos? ¿Descenderá Saúl, como ha oído tu siervo? Jehová Dios de Israel, te ruego que lo declares a tu siervo. Y Jehová dijo: Sí, descenderá.

12 Dijo luego David: ¿Me entregarán los vecinos de Keila a mí y a mis hombres en manos de Saúl? Y Jehová respondió: Os entregarán.

13 David entonces se levantó con sus hombres, que eran como seiscientos, y salieron de Keila, y anduvieron de un lugar a otro. Y vino a Saúl la nueva de que David se había escapado de Keila, y desistió de salir”.

1 Samuel 23: 11 – 13

Ahora, si piensas que los contrafácticos no tienen valor de verdad, entonces debes de decir que estos pasajes de las Escrituras no son ni verdaderos ni falsos. Pero ello parece absurdo. Si crees que la palabra de Dios es inerrante (así como yo lo creo, y así como implican pasajes como Proverbios 30:5 y 2 Timoteo 3:16), entonces una negación del conocimiento medio parece implicar que la doctrina de la inerrancia bíblica es falsa. Y peor aún, no solo la inerrancia bíblica, sino la inerrancia divina también (dado que fue Jesús quien afirmó el contrafáctico en Mateo 11, y fue Dios respondiendo a David en 1 Samuel 23). Si Dios no posee conocimiento medio, entonces no solo su Palabra no es inerrante, sino ¡él tampoco lo es!

3 Cuando hablamos del Libre Albedrío y la Providencia Divina, el Molinismo es una inferencia a la Mejor Explicación

Cuando hablamos de la providencia divina, yo sólo conozco tres opciones posibles. Dos de ellas son extremos inaceptables. Por una parte, podríamos estar de acuerdo con el Calvinista de que Dios causalmente determina todo lo que ocurre. La manera en la que Dios ordena providencialmente la historia humana es determinando cada pensamiento, palabra o acción de cada ser humano que ha vivido en la Tierra. En esta perspectiva, no hay libre albedrío (excepto, tal vez, una libertad compatibilista, pero no creo que la definición compatibilista del libre albedrío sea “libre” en algún sentido significativo de la palabra). Hay varios problemas con esta perspectiva. Uno de ellos siendo que ésta perspectiva lógicamente implica que Dios es el autor del mal; es decir, Dios es realmente responsable por cada hecho malvado que ha ocurrido en la historia. Si Dios causalmente determinó las acciones de todos, entonces la razón por la cual ellos hacen acciones malvadas es porque Dios esencialmente los hizo hacerlas. Si Dios los hizo hacerlas, entonces Él es finalmente el responsable por el mal de este mundo. Entonces Dios sería el pecador último, Él sería malvado. Dado que sabemos tanto de la teología natural (Argumento Moral y Argumento Ontológico) y de las Escrituras que Dios no es malvado, por lo tanto, el determinismo divino no es verdad. Además, hay una gran cantidad de Escritura que no tiene sentido lógico a menos que se presuponga el libre albedrío cuando se leen pasajes bíblicos. Por ejemplo, todos esos lugares en donde Dios se enoja hacia el pecado y procede a castigar a las personas por el mal que han cometido. Ello no tendría sentido si Dios determinara tus acciones. Si Dios determinara sus acciones, ¿por qué se enojaría con ellos? Si no le agradó lo que esas personas hicieron, ¿por qué no las determinó a hacer cosas que lo harían feliz? Además, ¿acaso no es injusto castigar a personas si tú eres la razón por la que ellos hicieron lo que hicieron?

Por otro lado, tenemos la perspectiva del libre albedrío libertariano y el conocimiento previo simple del Arminianismo. Esta perspectiva enseña que todos los seres humanos tienen libre albedrío libertariano (lo que significa que tenemos la habilidad tanto de escoger como de refrenarnos de escoger entre varias alternativas frente a nosotros, y también de que somos el origen último de nuestras acciones, y no había nada prohibiéndonos de escoger diferente a lo que hemos escogido). Sin embargo, como el Calvinista, el Arminiano afirma que Dios tiene conocimiento previo simple. Es decir, Dios conoce lo que SERÁ en el futuro, lo que todos libremente ESCOGEREMOS, pero él no sabe todos los futuros posible que hubieran sido si hubiéramos tomado decisiones diferentes. Él no conoce los contrafácticos de la libertad creatural. Esto también crea un problema también. Si Dios solo conoce el futuro real, y no cómo el futuro hubiera sido si las cosas fueran un poco diferentes, entonces, ¿cómo podemos explicar la providencia de Dios a través de la historia humana?

Imagina que Dios crea un mundo, y Él solo conoce el futuro real, pero él no conoce los contrafácticos de la libertad creatural. ¿Qué hubiera pasado si Judas, Pilato, o Caifás no hubieran hecho las decisiones requeridas para crucificar a Jesús? ¿Qué hay si Judas libremente escoge no traicionar a Jesús? O ¿qué hay si Pilato no sucumbe a la presión de la multitud para crucificarle? Ciertamente, Dios sería capaz de prever sus decisiones libres, pero Él no sería capaz de hacer algo al respecto sin violentar su libertad. Y en este caso, no habría redención porque Jesús no hubiera sido crucificado. Ahí quedó nuestra redención por nuestros pecados. En el Arminianismo, parece que Dios simplemente es suertudo de que estos eventos tomaron el curso que Él quería que tomaran. En el Arminianismo, Dios simplemente no parece tener el control soberano que la Biblia describe que Él tiene.

Dado que ni el Calvinismo ni el Arminianismo son opciones aceptables (porque implican consecuencias absurdas), la única opción restante es el Molinismo. El Molinismo puede explicar de la mejor manera la providencia meticulosa de Dios sobre la historia humana mientras al mismo tiempo explica el libre albedrío genuino. En el Molinismo, Dios tiene tres momentos lógicos de conocimiento; natural, medio y libre.  El conocimiento natural de Dios es su conocimiento de todas las posibilidades y verdades necesarias, todo lo que podría suceder. El conocimiento medio de Dios es el conocimiento de todos los contrafácticos, todo lo que sucedería. El conocimiento libre de Dios es el conocimiento de lo que realmente va a suceder en el futuro, lo que sucederá. El conocimiento natural de Dios es un conocimiento de todos los mundos posibles, su conocimiento medio es un conocimiento de todos los mundos viables, y su conocimiento libre es un conocimiento del mundo real. El conocimiento libre es un resultado del decreto eterno de Dios (es decir, escoger cuál mundo viable actualizar [hacer real]).

Pienso que esta perspectiva explica de la mejor manera la orquestación de Dios de los eventos humanos y también permite afirmar una perspectiva fuerte de la libertad humana. En el Molinismo, Dios conoce cuales personas situar en aquellas posiciones en el primer siglo para hacer que Jesús sea crucificado. Él sabía que si Caifás era el sumo sacerdote en el primer siglo, entonces él libremente condenaría a Jesús en base a blasfemia y lo llevaría a Pilato para la ejecución. Él sabía que si Pilato era prefecto en el primer siglo, entonces él libremente cumpliría las demandas de la multitud. Y Él sabía que si Judas naciese en el tiempo y lugar en el que en realidad nació, entonces él se volvería un discípulo de Jesús por un tiempo y libremente escogería traicionar a Jesús con el Sanedrín. En el Molinismo, Dios providencialmente produjo la crucifixión al actuar respecto a su conocimiento de cómo las personas libremente actuarían si fueran puestas en esas posiciones. Dios las produjo al situarlos en esas circunstancias, y las personas produjeron estos eventos desde su propio libre albedrío porque ellos fueron los que hicieron esos contrafácticos verdaderos de ellos mismos.

Y al contrario de la opinión popular Arminiana, esto no es determinista. Dios no escoge qué contrafacticos son verdaderos. Las Personas deciden qué contrafácticos son verdaderos. Todo lo que Dios hace es actuar en base a su conocimiento de los contrafácticos de la libertad creatural.

Por ejemplo, Dios puede conseguir que Bob escoja la acción A en lugar de la acción B si lo crea en las circunstancias S. Porque Dios sabía que si Bob estuviera en las circunstancias S, él libremente escogería la acción A en lugar de la B”. Dios logra que Bob escoja A al situarlo en esas circunstancias. Pero Bob no debía [necesitaba] escoger A. Bob bien podía haber escogido B en su lugar. Nada determinó o coaccionó a Bob a escoger A y nada le prohibía a Bob escoger B. Bob pudo haber escogido B y haberse refrenado de escoger A. Si lo hubiera hecho, entonces el conocimiento medio de Dios no hubiera contenido la proposición “Si Bob estuviera en S, él escogería A en lugar de B”. No. Dios hubiera sabido “Si Bob estuviera en S, él escogería B en lugar de A”. Dios no decreta cuales contrafácticos de la libertad creatural son verdad, son las criaturas las que lo hacen. Todo lo que Dios hace es escoger cuales son las circunstancias en las que nos encontramos al determinar cuándo y dónde nacemos (como Hechos 17:26 dice).

El Molinismo me parece la mejor explicación. Por cuestiones de espacio no puedo enlistar los pasajes bíblicos mostrando que Dios tiene providencia divina sobre la historia y los pasajes que muestran que los seres humanos tienen libre albedrío libertariano, pero las enseñanzas están ahí, y creo que mi perspectiva es la mejor para reconciliar esos dos conjuntos de verdades bíblicas. Yo si pienso que Proverbios 16:9 enseña simultáneamente el libre albedrío y la providencia divina (o al menos parece que lo hace), lo cito a continuación:

El corazón del hombre piensa su camino; Mas Jehová endereza sus pasos”.
Proverbios 16:9

Eso parece reflejar la declaración de Randy Everist (del blog “Possible Worlds”) sobre el Molinismo en un comentario de Facebook, la cual es “Nosotros escogemos lo que haríamos, y basado en eso, Dios escoge lo que haremos”.

[En la siguiente parte se publicarán las últimas dos razones y la conclusión por las que Evan Minton considera que el molinismo es verdad]

Recursos recomendados en Español:

Robándole a Dios (tapa blanda), (Guía de estudio para el profesor) y (Guía de estudio del estudiante) por el Dr. Frank Turek

Por qué no tengo suficiente fe para ser un ateo (serie de DVD completa), (Manual de trabajo del profesor) y (Manual del estudiante) del Dr. Frank Turek

 


Evan Minton es un apologista cristiano y bloguero en Cerebral Faith (www.cerebralfaith.net). Es el autor de “Inference To The One True God” (Inferencia al único Dios verdadero) y “A Hellacious Doctrine” (Doctrina infernal). Ha participado en varios debates que pueden ser visto en la sección “Mis debates” de Cerebral Faith. El Sr. Minton vive en Carolina del Sur, EE. UU.

Traducido por Raúl Jaramillo de Lira

By Xavier Gonzalez

In Part I the author addresses the common objections presented by some Christians who consider philosophy to be anti-biblical.

Consequences of denying philosophy

In an article by FreeThinkingMinistries (FTM), he mentions about 5 problems of theology “ without philosophy” [1] , I will summarize the 5 points he mentions and focus on 3 given their importance. According to the article, the problems would be:

1) The belief that one can engage in theological practices having divorced oneself from all one’s philosophical presuppositions is itself a philosophical presupposition. That is, self-defeating/self-refuting.

2) Saying that we should do theology without philosophy really only means that we should interpret the scriptures without reasoning about them or without having reasoned about how we are going to apply the interpretation assigned to them . In other words, it leads to irrationalism and would lead us to extreme relativism.

3) With that in mind, given the exclusion of philosophy that the “Without-Philosophy” view assumes, it simply remains without any other resources available to the theologian, inferential or otherwise, that can be used to assess the truth value of a theological claim since any resources given to the theologian will be, at root, philosophical. That is, even though we may know various doctrinal concepts, it gives us no guarantee of their truth or falsity or for that matter their philosophical implications.

4) In short, it is through reflection on the prior philosophical commitments that underpin a doctrine that it helps to weigh its plausibility. That is, it helps us to reject false and misleading ideas (yes, as Paul would warn us).

5) If Christians exemplify more seriousness in their beliefs in terms of being able to recognize their own presuppositions, the cultural perception of them will change. That is, we will not be mocked by society and Christianity will be seen as blind belief.

The 3 points I want to emphasize in the 5 that FTM mentions, is that if we are constant in a theology without philosophy, we would be in the middle of a dangerous and catastrophic web. Imagine the following, you are listening to the radio and the station gives a program on Christian doctrines, the announcer begins to talk about the attribute of divine eternity, he exposes several verses about God being eternal, and someone calls the announcer of the program, and the user begins to ask difficult questions, about how God would relate to time? How is God not affected by time? If God is timeless, does he know that it is 4:00 am in Dubai? What is an eternal Being?… And you are attentively listening to the user’s questions and then listening to the announcer’s answers, and the announcer says: “I’m sorry friend, I only abide by what is said in the word and not by philosophical speculations,” you are shocked by such questions and even more so without having answers from the announcer, then you begin to meditate on the user’s questions and without finding an answer, you ask yourself, What do I believe?

Well, this is the problem, that if you are ignorant of philosophical problems and reject philosophy, you will be deceived, you will not have tools to help you evaluate the proposals and ultimately you will have bad theology. And to give a very common example, this has happened a lot by those who support scientism.

The philosophical necessity in Christianity

As we have seen, the consequences of a Christianity without philosophy are harmful, although we should not stop there, and the other side of the coin points out to us many contributions that philosophy has made to Christianity and the philosopher Paul M. Gould & James K. Dew Jr. give us 3 reasons, which are:

1) Philosophy is strategic for evangelism. As Christians we are called to be faithful witnesses for Christ. We want every person on the face of the earth to ask and answer the question, “What do you think about Jesus Christ?” Unfortunately, in our day and age it can be difficult to get people to seriously consider this question. Philosophy helps us understand the collective mindset, its value systems, and the emotional response patterns of the culture. Christian philosophy can help expose the false ideas that keep people from considering Christianity as a genuine option. God has given us minds, and He wants us to use them to help others see the truth, goodness, and beauty of Jesus and the gospel. He wants us to use philosophy (and more so theology) to show that Christianity is faithful to the way the world is and the way the world should be.

2) Second, philosophy prepares us for ministry. I (Paul) can’t tell you the number of times I’ve had students—usually as a prospective pastor or even a doctoral student of theology or some aspect of Christian ministry—ask me why they should take logic. How would logic help them become better preachers or church leaders or Bible students? At first, when I was asked this question, I was dumbfounded. It seemed obvious to me that God wants us to be good thinkers, and logic is one of the tools that will help in that area. Now, when I’m asked to justify the need to take logic, I simply invite them to “come and see.” Fortunately, I’ve found that these same students become the most ardent advocates of the use and benefit of logic for preaching, ministry, and Bible study.

3) Philosophy plays a key role in our spiritual formation toward Christ. Christians are commanded to “be transformed by the renewing of your mind” (Rom. 12:2 ESV) and to love God with all our minds (Matt. 22:37-39). Part of this process is seeing Jesus for who He is: the source of all wisdom and knowledge (Col. 2:3). Jesus is beautiful, and we rightly worship Him as such. But Jesus is also brilliant—the smartest person in history. As Dallas Willard presses, “Can we seriously imagine that Jesus could be Lord if He weren’t smart?” The obvious answer is no! As followers of Jesus, we too must cultivate moral and intellectual virtue. God has given each of us a mind. He wants us to use it for His glory. He wants us to live life rightly related to reality and to God, to each other, to ourselves, and to our purpose. Philosophy can help in all of these areas. [2]

Conclusion

In conclusion, we can say that the scriptures do not say that we should emphatically reject philosophy, and as we saw in the section on the problem of a theology without philosophy and its necessity, on the one hand the Christian must embrace philosophy, but be attentive to bad philosophy, as CS Lewis would say: Good philosophy must exist, if for no other reason, because bad philosophy needs to be answered. And the Christian philosopher Peter S. Williams invites us to philosophy with the following words:

Philosophy is an artistic discipline, and for the Christian it should be a spiritual discipline. After all, Jesus supported the idea that true spirituality requires one to love the Lord one’s God with all one’s heart, with all one’s mind, and with all one’s strength, and to love one’s neighbor as oneself. [3]

References:

[1] https://freethinkingministries.com/cuales-son-algunos-de-los-problemas-con-la-teologia-sin-filosofia/

[2] Philosophy: A Christian introduction pages 18-21

[3] A Faithful Guide to Philosophy page 18

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek  

 


Xavier Gonzalez is from Venezuela and is dedicated to the study of philosophy, early Christianity and theology. He converted to Christianity at the age of 15. He managed the Me Lo Contó Un Ateo website and is in charge of the apologetics section of the Iglesia Cristiana la gracia website ( http://www.iglesialagracia.org ).

By Xavier Gonzalez

I have often encountered Christians who say “Philosophy is bad”, “we only need the scriptures and no philosophy”, “philosophy is from the devil” and statements like that, but I consider that these ideas that they try to sustain, in the end, are false. The notion that the Christian must reject philosophy is somewhat absurd and catastrophic. And in this article I will mention why and the need for philosophy in Christianity.

To the surprise of some (from what I have been able to study) throughout the history of the Church they have been able to know how to use tweezers (and others not) to approve and reject or modify the theses of various philosophers, even this we can see in certain passages of the Bible where Paul cites certain pagans as in Acts 17:28, where the part that says: “For in Him we live, and move, and have our being [or exist] … For we are his offspring” are quotes attributed to both Aratus (310 BC) and Epimenides of Cretans (600 BC), which already starting from here, we can see that Paul was not against philosophy at all, but wait, what happens with Colossians 2:8? Did Paul change his mind? Was it hypocritical Paul to quote philosophers in his speech in Athens when in Colossae he says not to be carried away by those who use philosophical arguments? Did Paul contradict himself? And my answer is no, Paul neither contradicted himself, nor was he a hypocrite, and much less did he change his mind.

Before moving on to the points of why a Christian should not reject philosophy, it will be appropriate to give the context of Colossians 2:8. According to the verse it tells us the following:

“Be on your guard so that no one takes you captive through empty and deceptive philosophy that follows human tradition, according to the principles of this world rather than according to Christ.” (NIV)

According to commentator AT Robertson, what Paul uses as Philosophos is not a condemnation of philosophy as such, but rather a false philosophy “Science falsely called” (pseudönumos gnösis, 1 Tim. 6:20) which is descriptive of Gnostic philosophy where many of its arguments are misleading and empty. [1] Even the Jamieson-Fausset-Brown commentary says: The apostle Paul does not condemn all philosophy, but the philosophy (so the Greek) of the Judeo-Oriental heretics at Colossae, which later developed into Gnosticism. [2] and according to the Ryrie Study Bible it mentions that Paul uses the vocabulary of the heretics, thus giving their true meaning, and then refutes them with their own terms that they used. Also the Partain-Reeves commentary mentions that according to Josephus, in those times any system of thought or moral discipline was called a philosophy. And in Judaism there were three philosophical schools, which were Pharisees, Sadducees and Essenes.

And if this is not enough, Moyer Hubbard’s team.org writes:

“Looking now at Colossians and the specific context of chapter 2, we find Paul addressing a local assembly that had been infiltrated by a form of false teaching that threatened to undermine the gospel he preached. Paul does not give us enough information to identify precisely what sect or ‘philosophy’ he is describing. However, there are some clues that suggest it was perhaps a syncretistic hybrid of Jewish mystical practices and pagan folk belief: he mentions the observance of special days, including the Sabbath (v. 16); visionary experience and worship of angels (v. 18); submission to the ‘elemental spirits of the world’ (v. 20); and abstinence (vv. 21,23). Paul is clearly attacking a peculiar form of religious speculation, but it is impossible to identify it with any of the major schools of philosophy we know from the Greco-Roman world. In fact, it is important to note that the Greek word philosophia (and its Latin cognate) had a variety of meanings in this period and, depending on the context, could be translated as ‘religion’, ‘speculation’ or ‘inquiry’” [3] .

In that case, using Colossians 2:8 to condemn philosophy would not be appropriate because it would be misinterpreting the verse. So we can safely say that Paul was not in any strict sense condemning philosophy as such, but rather a philosophy that (1) followed the principles of this world and (2) was not in conformity with Christ . Now that these doubts have been cleared up, let us address both the why and the need for philosophy in Christianity. [ In the next part of this article ].

References:

[1] Commentary on the Greek text of the NT, AT Robertson

[2] Jamieson-Fausset-Brown Commentary

[3] https://www.equip.org/article/is-colossians-28-a-warning-against-philosophy/

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek  

 


Xavier Gonzalez is from Venezuela and is dedicated to the study of philosophy, early Christianity and theology. He converted to Christianity at the age of 15. He managed the Me Lo Contó Un Ateo website and is in charge of the apologetics section of the Iglesia Cristiana la gracia website ( http://www.iglesialagracia.org ).

 

Skeptics sometimes portray Christians as both “unreasonable” and “irrational.” Christian culture only compounds the problem when it advocates a definition of “faith” without evidence. Is true faith blind? How do true believers respond to doubt? What is the relationship between faith and reason? Richard Dawkins once said:

“Many of us saw religion as harmless nonsense. Beliefs may lack any evidence, but we thought, ‘If people need a crutch for consolation, where’s the harm?’ 9/11 changed everything.”

This view of the Christian faith is common among skeptics and believers alike. Critics think that Christians accept truths without any justificatory support, and many Christians embrace the claims of Christianity unaware of the strong evidence that supports our worldview. Dawkins is right when he argues against forming beliefs without proof. People who accept truths without any examination or need for evidence are likely to believe myths and make bad decisions.

Christians are called to a reasonable faith

Christians, on the other hand, are not called to make decisions without compelling evidence. The God of the Bible does not call His children to blind obedience. The Gospels themselves are an important form of direct evidence; the testimony of eyewitnesses who observed the life, ministry, death, and resurrection of Jesus. That is why Scripture repeatedly calls us to have a well-founded belief in Christ, and not to resort to the behavior of irrational animals:

Jude 1,4.10

4 For some people who do not have God have infiltrated your churches, claiming that God’s wonderful grace allows us to live immoral lives. The condemnation of such people was written long ago, for they have denied Jesus Christ, our only Lord and Master. 10 But these people scoff at things they do not understand. Like unreasoning animals, they do whatever their own instincts tell them, thus bringing about their own destruction.

The Bible uses this word “irrational” in a pejorative way; to be irrational is to act like a brute animal. God clearly wants more from beings created in His image.

Christians are called to an examined faith

Matthew 22, 37-38

“Jesus said to him, ‘You shall love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and with all your mind. This is the first and greatest commandment. ’”

This kind of faith is not afraid of challenges. In fact, Christians are encouraged to examine what they believe critically so that they can be fully convinced:

1 Thessalonians 5, 19-21

Do not quench the Spirit. Do not despise prophecies. Test everything; hold fast to what is good…

1 John 4, 1

Beloved, do not believe every spirit, but test the spirits to see whether they are from God, because many false prophets have gone out into the world.

Romans 14, 5

Let each one be fully convinced in his own mind.

2 Timothy 3, 14

But continue in the things which you have learned and have been assured of, knowing from whom you learned them…

Christians are called to a faith based on evidence

Critical examination requires us to investigate the evidence, and God holds evidence in high regard. He wants us to be convinced after examining the facts. Jesus values ​​the evidence and continually provides proof to make His case:

John 14, 11

“Believe me that I am in the Father and the Father is in Me; or at least, believe for the miracles themselves.”

Jesus continued to give evidence to his disciples even after his resurrection: Acts 1, 2-3

…until the day He was taken up, after He had given commandments through the Holy Spirit to the apostles whom He had chosen; to whom also He shewed Himself alive after His suffering by many infallible proofs, being seen of them over a period of forty days, and speaking of the things pertaining to the kingdom of God.

Early Christians understood the connection between reason, evidence, and faith, and they did not view these concepts as mutually exclusive. In fact, Paul often uses direct evidence to make his case for Christianity:

Acts 17, 30-31

“In ancient times God overlooked people’s ignorance of these things, but now he commands everyone everywhere to repent of their sins and return to him. For he has set a day to judge the world in righteousness by the man he has appointed, and he has shown everyone who this man is by raising him from the dead.”

Acts 17, 2-3

As was his custom, Paul went to the synagogue service and, for three days of rest in a row, he used the Scriptures to reason with the people.   He explained the prophecies and proved that the Messiah had to suffer and rise from the dead. He said: “This Jesus, of whom I speak to you, is the Messiah.”

Christians are called to present a case for faith:

When believers use their minds, investigate the evidence, and become convinced, something wonderful happens: We have the courage to stand up for what we believe using the same evidence, logic, and reasoning we so vigorously used to come to faith in the first place:

1 Peter 3:15

…worship Christ as the Lord of your life. Always be ready to give an explanation to anyone who asks about the hope you have, but do so with humility and respect.

Christians from all disciplines of inquiry and discovery have used their powers of reason to investigate the evidence. Christians are NOT irrational, and Christian faith is NOT blind. Christianity’s rich intellectual history calls each of us to a faith that is reasonable, examined, evidence-based, and ready to be presented. This kind of faith honors God and stands up to skeptical criticism and personal doubt.

Recommended resources in Spanish:

Stealing from God ( Paperback ), ( Teacher Study Guide ), and ( Student Study Guide ) by Dr. Frank Turek

Why I Don’t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist ( Complete DVD Series ), ( Teacher’s Workbook ), and ( Student’s Handbook ) by Dr. Frank Turek  

 


J. Warner Wallace is the author of Cold-Case Christianity, has a career spanning more than 25 years as a police officer and detective, holds a Master of Divinity from Golden Gate Baptist Theological Seminary, and is an adjunct professor of apologetics at BIOLA University.

Original Blog: http://bit.ly/2UPIWRt

By Evan Minton

Molinism is a view of soteriology. It has much in common with Arminianism. It teaches that God wants every human being to come to Christ in order to be saved (2 Peter 3:9; 1 Timothy 2:4), that Jesus died for every human being God has ever created or will create (John 3:16-18; 1 Timothy 2:6; 1 Timothy 4:10; 1 John 2:2; Hebrews 2:9), that human beings are totally depraved, that is, incapable of coming to Christ on their own, because Jesus said that no one can come to the Father unless the Father who sent Him draws them to Himself (John 6:44; John 6:65), and because of this inability to come to Christ in our own strength, God sends the Holy Spirit to convict the world of sin (John 16:8) and to draw every person into a relationship with Himself (John 12:32). Molinists also believe, like Arminians, that humanity has libertarian free will. Libertarian Free Will is different from compatibilism because it asserts that we are not causally determined to do what we do (there are no determining factors, although there are certain things that influence our decisions), and also that there is the possibility of doing the opposite. So if I choose A, I didn’t have to choose A. I could have chosen B. There was nothing to prevent me from holding back from choosing A and choosing B instead. Molinists believe that because of the enabling grace mentioned above, we have a choice to make. We can either receive salvation or reject it (Deuteronomy 30:15-19; Joshua 24:15).

Molinism differs from Arminianism in a small number of ways. This is a view called Middle Knowledge. What is Middle Knowledge? According to the Molinist, God has three kinds of knowledge. The first is God’s knowledge of necessary truths or natural knowledge. These are truths that are independent of God’s will and are non-contingent. This knowledge includes the full range of logical possibilities. Examples include statements like, “All bachelors are not married,” or “X cannot be A and not-A at the same time, in the same way, in the same place,” or “It is possible for X to happen,” or “It is impossible for squares to be triangular.” The second is called “Middle Knowledge” and contains the range of possible things that would have happened given certain circumstances, for example, “If Evan Minton chose to eat fish at this particular restaurant instead of a hamburger, he would get food poisoning and have a miserable weekend,” or “If Evan’s dog broke its leash and started chasing a squirrel, he would chase it.” The third type of knowledge is God’s free knowledge. This type of knowledge consists of contingent truths that are dependent on God’s will; that is, truths that God causes. Examples of this would include, “God became incarnate in the first century B.C.,” or “God created the universe.” This is knowledge that God possesses because he has chosen to cause it.

So according to the Molinist, God not only knows what will happen and what could happen, but He also knows what would happen. God literally knows everything there is to know about everything. He even knows the counterfactuals, (“If X happens, then Y would happen after it.”). This was beautifully illustrated in the Christmas movie It’s a Wonderful Life in which God shows George Bailey what the world would have been like without him. It’s a Wonderful Life shows God’s middle knowledge in that while God knew George Bailey was indeed going to be born when he was, He nevertheless knew what the world would have been like without him.

William Lane Craig calls Molinism “one of the most fruitful theological ideas ever conceived, for it would serve to explain not only God’s knowledge of the future but divine providence and predestination as well.” Under it, God retains a measure of divine providence without impeding human freedom. Since God possesses middle knowledge, He knows what an agent would freely do in a particular situation. So agent A, if placed in circumstances C, would freely choose option X over option Y. Therefore, if God wanted to bring about X, all God would do is, using His middle knowledge, actualize the world in which A was placed at C, and A would freely choose X. God retains an element of providence without nullifying A’s choice, and God’s purpose (the actualization of X) is accomplished.

This is a very profound insight into how God can accomplish His purposes without violating our free choices. God can get us to do what He wants us to do without causally determining us to do it.

I gave this explanation of what Molinism is again because there are many people who are not aware of it. Many Christians know about Arminianism and Calvinism, but Molinism seems to me to be the forgotten middle child of the soteriological family. Maybe that is not an accurate perception, but I think it is one I have because the name is not mentioned very commonly in debates about soteriology. It is usually presented as “Arminianism vs Calvinism” rather than “Arminianism, Molinism or Calvinism.” Maybe it is because Molinism is so similar to Arminianism that the two are mixed together. But in any case, even though I have already explained what Molinism is in a previous blog post, I wanted to do it again for those who are new to the perspective and/or have not read my previous post about it.

Anyway, since God can get us to do something freely by placing us in a set of circumstances, this presents a question.

Couldn’t God simply put everyone in circumstances where they would believe and be saved?

There is no single Molinist answer to this question. There are several. One answer is called Transworld Damnation, in which God saves all who would freely respond to his grace in any circumstance. The corollary of this is that all those lost would be lost no matter what set of circumstances God put them in or no matter what grace God provided. In Transworld Damnation, the answer is “no”—God could not have arranged things in such a way that everyone would end up saved, because some would freely not believe. I, however, find this view extraordinarily implausible. Do you expect me to believe that there is no circumstance, no world that God could actualize in which Christopher Hitchens would become a born-again Christian and be saved? Is there no circumstance in which God could put Caiaphas in which he would plead for Jesus and not Barabbas? Was Judas Iscariot destined for hell in any world that God actualized? I find this view to be stretching the boundaries of plausibility quite a bit. I mean, I suppose it’s possible that this is the case for some individuals . There are certain things that each of us would never do under any circumstances. But to say that this is the case for all the unsaved is a little hard to swallow.

Here is my perspective: Even though God desires all human beings to be saved and Jesus died for all, I do not think there is any world that God can actualize with as many people as this one has where every individual chooses to repent. It may well be the case that God cannot put every individual in just the right circumstances where God knows that if they were put in those circumstances, they would freely choose to repent and be saved. It may be impossible to produce every one of these circumstances in a single world. So while I believe that God desires that none should perish, it may not be possible to produce every circumstance in which God knows would stimulate a free response from all. It may even be the case that some circumstance in which one person is saved is a circumstance in which someone else is lost. For example, I read an article recently written by someone who said that it was through reading Richard Dawkins’ book The God Delusion that he decided to convert to the Christian faith. Why? It was because he said that the arguments against God and for atheism were so shoddy, so bad, that he concluded that atheism was indefensible. This prompted him to read works in favor of Christianity to see what they had to say about these issues, and that was enough to convince him that atheism is a sham. Now, what if this world is one in which Richard Dawkins became a Christian, say, at the age of 17? If that were the case, then he would never have written The God Delusion . And if that were the case, this person would never have read it and concluded that atheism is indefensible and that theism was a welcome alternative.

In this case, if Dawkins were saved, this other fellow might not have been. If this fellow were saved, it may be the case that this world is one where Dawkins is never saved.

So it could well be the case that no matter what world God chooses to create, there will be circumstances in which God knows that people will freely reject Him, while some will repent.

However, since we have libertarian free will, and our circumstances do not causally determine us to do what we do, no human being has any excuse for not repenting. All can be saved. People can act differently in the situations in which they are placed. God simply knows that they will not act differently. It is a would/would not situation and not a can/cannot situation. So no man can stand before God on the day of judgment and say, “If only you had put me in a particular situation, then I would have repented. But because you did not put me in that particular situation, I did not repent, and now here I stand before you condemned. So it is all your fault, God.” God will say, “No, you had the freedom to choose me or reject me. It was possible for you to do either no matter what situation I placed you in.” God gives prevenient and resistible grace to every individual (as Jesus said in John 12:32). This overcomes his inability to come to Him, mentioned by Jesus in John 6:44 and John 6:65, So even though there may be a possible world where Richard Dawkins is a born-again Christian, it is entirely possible for him to be [born again] in any world God actualizes, It is up to him whether he is or not.

In summary , I just said above that a) God wants all people to be saved; b) God has given man libertarian free will; c) even though God has put us in circumstances where He knows how we will act, there is a possibility to do otherwise. It’s not that I couldn’t reject Christ in the situation God put me in. It’s that God knew I wouldn’t; d) God gives prevenient and resistible grace to every human being so that their salvation would at least be possible; e) Whatever world God actualizes where man has free will in the libertarian sense, He cannot guarantee that every individual will accept Christ as their Savior.

 


Evan Minton is a Christian apologist and blogger at Cerebral Faith ( www.cerebralfaith.blogspot.com ). He is the author of “Inference To The One True God” and “A Hellacious Doctrine.” He has participated in several debates which can be viewed in the “My Debates” section of Cerebral Faith. Mr. Minton lives in South Carolina, USA.

[Original English blog not available]

Translated by Raul Jaramillo de Lira

Introduction

When one thinks about the debate between the Sovereignty of God and the genuine responsibility of man, two positions are commonly presented with which one can identify, Calvinism and Arminianism [1] . In general, these perspectives are characterized by an emphasis (or over-emphasis) on the Sovereignty of God and the Freedom of Man respectively.

This endless discussion has led us to believe that at the heart of this dilemma lies the different approaches by which Christians throughout history have sought to solve it. “Arminians have a humanistic and man-centered gospel, while Calvinists focus on God and His Glory,” some Calvinist brothers tell us. Is that true? Does the problem lie in the approach with which we approach this matter at hand? [2]

Before we get into the subject, we must analyze the different presuppositions with which each perspective attempts to resolve this tension. One of the differences between Arminians and Calvinists is their definition of human freedom. While Arminians subscribe to a libertarian philosophical view of freedom, Calvinists, who are determinists, generally subscribe to a compatibilist definition of freedom. This issue is crucial and must be clarified before beginning to discuss the positions, since in a discussion both sides can debate for hours without reaching any conclusion, simply because of the lack of clear and well-defined concepts. From this point on, I will change the terms Arminian and Molinist to Libertarian and Calvinist to Compatibilist. [3]

The most common definition of Libertarian Liberty with which some libertarians, specifically Molinists such as Luis de Molina, William Lane Craig, and Kenneth Keathley, identify themselves, is:

“Freedom can be considered as opposed to necessity. Thus, a free agent is said to be one who, given all the requirements for acting, can act and not act, or do one thing as well as its opposite.” [4]

“Not being caused to do something by causes other than oneself. It is entirely my responsibility how I choose, and nothing determines my choice. Sometimes philosophers call this “agent causation.” The agent herself is the cause of her actions. Her decisions are distinguished from chance events by being made by the agent herself for reasons the agent has in mind.” [5]

“Libertarianism is the view that the morally responsible agent is in some sense the source of his choices, and that prior conditions such as circumstances are not the ultimate determinant for that agent.” [6]

Some contemporary philosophers usually understand Libertarianism as that position that contains the following statements:

(L1) An agent acts with free will, or is morally responsible for an action, only if the action is not ultimately causally determined by anything or being outside the agent.

(L2) An agent acts with free will, or is morally responsible for an action, only if he or she could have acted otherwise.

(L3) An agent acts with free will, or is morally responsible for an action, only if his own intellect and will are the sole and final causes of his action [7] .

Which brings us to the purpose of this article, how does this work with regard to the grace of God? Compatibilists believe in strict monergism, God sends irresistible [8] or effective grace to individuals He has chosen in advance, so that when this grace comes to them, they are renewed and their desires are transformed, and so they respond in faith to that effective call of God. Note the adjective “effective,” that is, if a person is touched with irresistible grace, he will necessarily respond in faith. Therefore, the compatibilist can say that everything is a work and labor of God, there is nothing that man does in the process of salvation. Certain compatibilists, in adopting this monergistic view, commonly view any other view that differs from theirs as a Pelagian or synergistic view.

To answer this charge, in this article I will propose to reflect on an essay by Dr. Richard Cross [9] analyzing this charge on behalf of our Reformed brethren. Does any position that does not presuppose irresistible grace really fall within the Pelagian definition? Or is it possible to construct some plausible model that allows us to affirm the resistibility of divine grace without falling into Pelagianism?

Definitions and Terms

We must be very careful with our definitions. I have found that the terms “Pelagianism” and “semi-Pelagianism” are used without awareness of their meaning and implications. Dr. Cross generally defines these views in the following paragraph [10] :

“In the Council of Orange (529) canon 9, every good act we do is produced in us by God…. The condemned view is that we can bring about our own salvation in any sense.” [11]

If we read this in parallel with canon 3, where

“The view that God’s grace ‘can be conferred by human invocation’ is condemned.” [12]

Then we can agree with canon 5 of the Council of Orange,

“Canon 5 of the Council condemns the view that the beginning of faith in us is not through the working of the gift of grace. This constitutes a rejection of the semi-Pelagian view that the beginning of our justification is from us, not from God.” (Emphasis added) [13]

Taking this into account, we understand these systems as follows:

Pelagianism: We are the cause of our justification. [14]

Semi-Pelagianism: We are the beginning of our justification, but not the cause of our own justification. [15]

Irresistibility of Grace vs. Pelagianism

Once we understand these perspectives, it seems to me that we can agree with Dr. Cross when he says:

“Pelagianism and the irresistibility of grace are logically incompatible. The problem arises since it is not so obvious whether it is possible to reject Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism, while still maintaining the resistibility of grace.” [16]

That is, we recognize that if grace is irresistible, then it is impossible for us to be the cause of our own justification [17] therefore, Pelagianism is false. Likewise, if we can cause our own justification, then grace is not irresistible.

“If either Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism is true, the irresistibility of grace is false.”

However,

“If either Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism is false, it is not necessary that the irresistibility of grace be true.” [18]

Cross tells us that while it is easy to recognize that the irresistibility of grace and Pelagianism/semi-Pelagianism are mutually exclusive, it is not so obvious to conclude that if we reject the irresistibility of grace we necessarily fall into these systems. In other words, to reject the irresistibility of grace is not necessarily to embrace Pelagianism .

“The resistibility of grace does not imply accepting either Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism.” [19]

It is also important to mention that the author points out:

“What unites the seven models of the offer of grace is the belief that justifying grace – justification – is resistible.” [20]

This will then imply that irresistible grace is presupposed to be false. Cross plans to explain why he thinks there are models that possibly allow us to maintain the resistibility of grace and at the same time reject Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism in a coherent and consistent way.

At this point Cross acknowledges that he has come to an issue that is apparently still being debated in academic circles. Both Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism involve the concept of cause in their definitions and failure to clarify what can be counted as a cause and what cannot has been the source of much misunderstanding when I have discussed these issues. This is why Cross himself acknowledges:

“It is difficult to determine what is a sufficient cause for some state of affairs, as well as what would be accepted as an initialization of a process that results in a certain state of affairs. I do not pretend to lay down principles for these analyses, because I am not sure that such principles exist in all cases, but I rely on intuitions. These seem to be firm enough to bear the weight I am putting on them. They are the same sort of principles considered reasonable and sufficient for the moral judgments we make in everyday life. But I will leave the plausibility of my intuitions to be judged by the reader.” [21]

It will be intuition itself that will tell us whether something can be counted as a sufficient cause for a state of affairs, in this case, for the justification of a person.

Introduction to the Seven Models

  1. COVENANT THEOLOGY

This perspective can be summarized as follows:

“God promises to justify—or at least offer grace—to anyone who satisfies certain minimal ethical conditions.” [22]

I think it is quite clear what is being argued in this perspective, simply,

“Person X freely promises to do action A if person Y acts in a manner W.” [23]

If God is X and Y is any human being, God promises to do A , that is, to justify, if Y performs or fulfills W .

If YW .

Then, XA .

We see then that person Y is solely the cause of W and not of A. While X is the sole and total cause of A. If we believe that God freely promises to bring justification to a person if that person meets certain moral requirements, then we can affirm that God is the cause of justification and not us.

I can already imagine the criticisms that arise in the minds of our deterministic brothers: “this system does not take into account the total depravity of man,” “this system ultimately amounts to salvation by works,” and a few others.

Domino effect

We know that God never breaks his promise, so if person Y fulfills the conditions ( W ), then he will necessarily receive grace and be saved. But this means that the cause of the ultimate effect is Y , since:

“And causing W is sufficient for X to cause A, Y is therefore the final cause of A.” [24]

Cross proposes an analogy that invites us to reflect on the conditions under which we assign blame to other people.

“Imagine an agent who is ‘programmed’ in such a way that he is always prevented from breaking his promise. The agent… is not, however, conspicuously good in any other sense. Suppose this agent freely promises to perform a bad action whenever I act in accordance with an obligation of mine.” [25]

I think we understand the issue at hand, can a person S be guilty or responsible for the actions of another agent P who has freely promised to act evilly if person S acts in a specific way? Cross tells us:

It seems to me that I cannot be blamed for the evil actions this person causes, even if I am aware of the promise he has made. The reason is because this person’s promise was free. He did not have to make it. It is his free promise that causes him to act the way he does, not my actions. [26]

I did not cause the evil agent’s actions, it was his promise that caused him to act evilly.

Cross concludes,

Pari passu, then, it is God’s free covenant that causes salvation in this medieval or Arminian view. [27]

Salvation by Works

But if the works I do meet the requirements God has imposed for salvation,

“Is this perspective not summed up in my actions deserving justification?” [28]

I believe this objection is the most common one to any view that denies the irresistibility of grace. For now, we will focus on the weight of this objection to God’s free covenant view of salvation.

The answer, as far as I can see, would simply be a straightforward ‘no’. For nothing we have said says that the works we do merit salvation in such a way that God must save us. That is, no one has claimed that fulfilling the requirements puts God in a position where he must necessarily save us.

“If we forget for a moment the divine promise, merit would only exist in the case where my actions placed God under some kind of obligation to justify me, or something functionally equivalent to obligation. And—leaving aside the divine promise—such an obligation or quasi-obligation could only exist if the nature of my actions were such that they would morally require justification as a reward.” [29]

Now, if we think about it carefully, if our actions are of such a nature that they would morally require justification as a reward , then the divine promise would be unnecessary. Since God must save me because of my works, His covenant would be merely a legal clause, so to speak.

“But, so far, nothing I have said implies that the minimal requirements that need to be satisfied for justification are such that justification is morally necessary.” [30]

Cross does take into account something known as congruous merit [31] , that is, the merit of certain actions for which it is indeed appropriate for God to reward some action. This kind of merit is commonly spoken of in works of charity in the context of Catholicism [32] . But he says,

But we need not speak of congruous merit either. God’s promise could be entirely gratuitous or unnecessary [gratitous], and nothing in my actions would have any intrinsic meritorious value. Apart from the divine promise, they would be worthless, and not even worthy of appropriating God’s reward. [33]

That is, nothing in my works makes them suitable for God to reward them with saving grace. Nothing we have said leads us to that conclusion. So we are not talking about works that merit salvation.

Therefore, the covenant view is not Pelagianism.

Semi-Pelagianism?

We have seen that the view of Covenant theology succeeds in evading the charge of being Pelagian. But what about semi-Pelagianism? The crucial question is, what initiates the process of justification?

God’s promise?

A person’s satisfaction of the moral requirements for justification? [34]

Cross acknowledges that it is possible that this view might be considered semi-Pelagianism, but he is not sure that there is a strong argument for this. The defender of this view might stress to us that the initialization is the divine promise. However, he concedes that in the initialization process of justification the idea that the promise is the beginning is not very convincing either:

The promise seems too remote, causally, to be counted as the initialization of such an instance. The promise is more like a general condition for justification. It is rather like the machinery of justification and not so much a causal part in the process. The promise is a way of setting up the process of justification, but what initiates the process is human action. [35]

That is to say, the mere fact that the promise exists is not a sufficient cause that initiates the process, even if it is a necessary cause.

So, on the basis of what we have seen, this view can really be considered Semi-Pelagianism. But Cross admits that this is not the end of the argument:

Nevertheless, I do not believe that this is a sufficient argument to convince someone strongly planted in the anti-Pelagian framework of a covenant theology. Such a person might insist that God’s promise counts as the initialization of any process of justification and therefore deny that his view is Pelagian or semi-Pelagian. [36]

It will be up to the reader to decide whether covenant theology seems to him to be a perspective that effectively evades the charges of Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism. If one adopts this position, it will be his duty to demonstrate that the initialization process is entirely God’s.

A clarification is necessary at this point:

The following six views are not Semi-Pelagian because they all insist that the initiation of individual justification is the offer of God’s Grace to an individual. But, this offer of grace requires some form of acceptance. And this is in no sense prior to the offer of grace to an individual. [37]

If the reader is perceptive, he will notice that, unlike covenant theology, the question will not be what initiates the process of salvation , but rather, is acceptance the result of grace or is it a work that we do on our own? For, as Cross says,

The acceptance of grace cannot be the necessary result of a divine gift. If this gift is irresistible, then grace is irresistible. If the gift of acceptance is resistible, then the gift of acceptance also needs acceptance. Ad infinitum. [38]

That is, if our acceptance is a gift God has irresistibly given to us, then grace is indeed irresistible. Since I do not see it as plausible that we have an infinite regression from acceptance of gifts of grace to acceptance, the acceptance of grace must come from our own volition. But…

Is it possible to combine an anti-Pelagianism with some view in which human acceptance of the offer of grace is not the result of grace? [39]

With that question in mind, let’s dive into our analysis of the following perspective:

  1. SYNERGISM

In this perspective,

The acceptance of offered grace counts as a work—something which the person to whom the grace is offered actually does. It is a work which is entirely within the power of the agent, and entirely a result of the natural disposition and inclination of the agent. [40]

Of course, the mere mention of the word synergism will cause many, if not most, of our Reformed brethren to jump out of their seats and shout “Pelagianism!”

Cross argues that this perspective need not be Pelagian:

If we hold that Pelagianism boils down to the claim that we can sufficiently save ourselves by our own actions, then this version of synergism I am considering is not Pelagian. (Emphasis added) [41]

That is, if we define synergism as:

Synergism: Two necessary and sufficient causes in conjunction for our justification. [42]

Since we cannot sufficiently save ourselves, then it is not Pelagianism, no matter how much the defender of Irresistible Grace wants to claim it.

But, taking up the statements of previous councils, Cross reminds us:

However, if we read the Second Council of Orange, saying that no action of ours can have any causal role—even if it is not sufficient—in justification, then synergism in this case is Pelagianism. [43]

According to the council, “ we cannot in any sense cause our own salvation .” So synergism, by assigning a causal role to our acceptance, would in effect reduce itself to Pelagianism. Although, of course, this depends on how we read the council’s statements – is it in a strict sense? Or is there some flexibility, which would allow us to assign a role to acceptance and not fall into Pelagianism?

Some theologians in the past agreed with the strong interpretation since, if our own acceptance is required for justification, then God’s Grace is not completely reliable. [44]

That is, “If it requires us to accept grace, then we cannot put our trust for our salvation in God’s grace, but in our acceptance of it.” Or the classic argument, “then it is not God who saves you, but your acceptance of grace.” But Cross tells us that

However, this answer depends on accepting the doctrine of the irresistibility of grace, and for the purposes of this discussion, I am proceeding as if this doctrine were false. It seems to me that a question about the absolute reliability of grace is itself a question independent of Pelagianism. [45]

It seems to me that what Cross is trying to say is that people who make this objection presuppose that it is necessary for grace to be irresistible in order to trust God completely, and therefore it is a circular argument. However, there is another reason that Cross examines for accepting the strict reading of the councils.

The reason is that the offer of grace plus the acceptance by the individual could be considered as sequentially ordered parts in a process that ends in the salvation of the person.

In a sense one element in a process is not sufficient for the outcome of that process, it is merely necessary. And that is why some think this is Pelagianism. [46]

But the mere fact of a sequence in the process does not mean that one of the parts is a sufficient cause for it to be considered Pelagianism. Cross explains:

The sequential nature of a causal cooperation does not negate its being a cooperation, and so does not necessitate that the action late in the process be a sufficient cause for the effect. So Synergism would reduce to Pelagianism only if one thinks that ascribing a causal role to human activity in justification is Pelagianism. And it is not clear that a reading of the Council requires such an interpretation. [47]

So while it is not Semi-Pelagianism, it is not clear that Synergism is not Pelagianism. It all depends on how we read the council’s statements. Personally, I reject this kind of synergism because I reject the idea that man has any causal role in salvation. And that is why I am more in agreement with the following theories that start from the idea that there is no need for a real, positive act on the part of the individual in relation to grace.

I think it is possible to maintain that no act of acceptance is needed for divine grace to be received by a person to be justified, and that grace, however, can be resisted. [48]

For the following three perspectives, Cross makes clear what some of the presuppositions he will start from will be:

If a person P accepts grace it means that P does not resist the total execution of some action A, which in some resistible way is produced by God in P. [49]

In Cross’ words, for the following three perspectives:

The basic idea is that in someone whom God has chosen for justification, the reception of grace is the default position; grace is received automatically unless the person maintains an active block to the reception of grace—that is, unless the person actively resists grace. [50]

  1. SUPERNATURAL INCLINATION

The third perspective that Cross examines is summarized as follows:

The relevant action is the causal result of a supernatural inclination. Such an inclination would be irresistibly given by God to a person, such that the inclination is sufficient for the action (unless it is impeded). The performance of the action counts as the acceptance of the grace. [51]

Ironically, Cross appeals to a kind of irresistible grace which is given to an agent. However, this grace does not irresistibly determine this agent to accept the effect of this grace, namely salvation. This grace is a sufficient causal factor to produce the effect, such that, if nothing prevents this grace from continuing its course, the agent will be justified.

Let us also understand that having an inclination toward grace is not the same as producing salvation in ourselves. So the charge of Pelagianism has been successfully evaded. For,

The inclination here is a tendency to perform an act, such that, if nothing intervenes, this act is produced. And acting in accordance with the inclination does not require any further causal cooperation on the part of the agent. (Emphasis added) [52]

That is, we do not require the agent to cooperate or act in any way to produce the effect. But simply,

The agent is not required to want or choose the relevant action A, but it is required that the agent does not want/choose/deliberately do something other than A. That is, it is not required that P wants A, but it is required that P does not want not-A. [53]

Where A is a morally good action. Although in theory, it is irrelevant which action A is .

However, the objection will immediately be raised, “Not wanting not-A is wanting A,” and therefore the effect would be a product of human action, as Cross recognizes,

The action, however, would count as a relevant action of a human person, since it is produced by something internal to the person, that is, the inclination.

A similar example. Consider an involuntary but controllable act such as blinking. My blinking is on automatic: I usually don’t want it, or even consciously cause it. But I can prevent it if I wish, at least for a while. I understand it in that I naturally have an inclination to blink, and the inclination is sufficient for the action. [54]

One could remain firm in saying that such an inclination is of divine origin and that therefore there is no synergism. Initial grace is irresistible and therefore there is nothing in man that produces this grace, unless it is conferred by God.

The divine inclination is sufficient (unless impeded) for an action A that constitutes the acceptance of grace, and this sufficiency means that the creature need not desire or choose A, or in some other causally additional way cooperate in A. [55]

But Cross admits,

Still, any causal contribution to the action internal to the agent may be felt to involve some kind of synergism. For, even if it is natural or divinely endowed in some special way, it is still the inclination of the agent, and as such is independent of the divine causal activity in the execution of the action. [56]

As already mentioned, this might imply synergism or even, it seems to me, an argument could be made to say that this position could be reduced to Semi-Pelagianism, but that is outside the scope of this paper. This, however, brings us to the description of our fourth perspective.

  1. SUPERNATURAL CAUSATION

As the name suggests,

The relevant action is produced directly by God—and not by means of an inclination. God produces the complete mechanism in which some action A consists. [57]

As we said above, some may take not-willing or not-resisting A to be willing or doing A , given its causal connection to God’s grace. And Cross seeks to evade this with his fourth view,

This view involves a distinctive claim, that the agent’s not willing/choosing/doing not-A consists in the agent’s desiring* A. [58]

However , wanting* something is not the same as doing something. So the mere fact of wanting A is not a cause of A.

The notion that an interior act of will, such as the agent willing* A is distinct from the agent doing A. [59]

But from this perspective,

Could an agent want* A and there be a sense in which the agent’s desire is not a causally necessary condition for A to be realized? [60]

That is, can this view hold that God is the causer of A without the agent P having a causal role in the realization of A ?

Cross discusses two ways to answer “yes” to this question:

From the above, we established that A is produced by God. God separates whatever causal mechanisms obtain between the inner act—desiring A—and the outer act—doing A. Choosing or willing* has no causal role, since God’s action remains sufficient unless prevented. The creature’s choice or willing is counterfactually sufficient: It would have been sufficient if God had not been causally responsible for fully performing the action. [61]

So the causal role of the agent is secondary, not necessary. All that is necessary is the causal role of God and that the agent does not resist God. The second way Cross says we can answer this question affirmatively is:

A is causally overdetermined and sufficiently produced by God, and sufficiently produced by the created agent. We can claim both that A is produced by God, and that A is produced by the creature. Under this option we need to claim that A is salvific merely in the case where it is true that A is produced by God, without regard to the truth of the statement that A is produced by the creature. So the relevant salvific statement is that A is produced by God, and so Pelagianism is avoided. [62]

It seems to me that one could say that, in this context, action A could be said to have an excess of sufficient causes. A is produced by both God and the creature. But in the salvific context, the only cause of A is God, and the fact that the agent produced A is irrelevant.

I find this view somewhat redundant and confusing; I think that an excess of sufficient causes is unnecessary. The proponent of Supernatural Causation seems to be telling us that, although God and the agent caused A , A is only salvific because God brought it about and not because the agent brought it about.

The fifth view known to many as the Ambulance model is one that is embraced by a large number of Molinists. Kirk MacGregor appeals to it as a model that is consistent with and compatible with the doctrine of total or radical depravity held by our Reformed brethren.

  1. AMBULANCE MODEL

This is the model that I find most persuasive of all the models explained by Cross. This model has been popularized in Dr. Kenneth Keathley’s book Salvation & Sovereignty , although the ambulance analogy was Cross’s original, hence the name. I’ll venture to say that it is the most popular theory in the Molinist camp, since the doctrine appears to most effectively uphold God’s sovereignty in salvation while at the same time upholding the libertarian freedom of human beings.

The main reason for this theory goes back to Augustine, who sought to formulate a position that rejected that of his contemporary Pelagius, without making human beings mere tools in the hands of God, robbing us of the personality that He endowed us with. Augustine sought to formulate a model that would allow us to give all the credit to God for salvation and at the same time place all the blame for condemnation on the person.

In view four, Cross seems to be telling us that it is at least possible for the agent to want to do A. But again, the determinist will immediately point to the radical depravity of man.

So this perspective of the ambulance tells us,

The action A itself is simply produced by God, without any causal origin in the person, or in an internal act of will. The created person wills neither A nor non-A; the person is simply indifferent to A. [63]

That is, here not wanting* A does not mean wanting* not-A but simply being indifferent to A. If we assume that A is the acceptance of grace, then God is the one who produces A in us , but this in the case in which we are indifferent to grace, that is, in the case in which we do not accept grace (wanting* A) but neither do we reject it (wanting* not-A ).

God moves the person as a puppet: God produces the complete movements of which action A consists. Unlike view 4, the moved person is not an act of self-will. There is no action in the creature. But the divine movement can be sufficient unless it is impeded. For prior to A, the creature can will*, choose, or do not-A. [64]

To be honest, the opening part of the above quote may be problematic for any non-determinist Christian. Moving the person around like a puppet? We are falling into precisely what we want to refute. But the ambulance analogy helps us see why this is not the case:

“Suppose… that I wake up to find that I am riding in an ambulance. Suppose also that at any moment that I am conscious of being in the ambulance, I have the option of not being there. Perhaps I can simply ask the driver to stop and let me out. If I do not do this, then I do not prevent the action being done to me—transporting me to the hospital, or whatever. But by the same token—I do not contribute to it, other than counterfactually (i.e., by not preventing it). Does not preventing A reduce to willing or doing A? Not generally, given the coherence of the notion of an inner act of will… If I do not do something, I remain in the ambulance. But it would be strange to describe this case as me going to the hospital or [me transporting myself to the hospital] (in contrast to me being brought to the hospital).” [65]

The analogy clearly reflects what was previously said, if the person is inside the ambulance he can get out at any time, but if he does not get out it does not mean that he transported himself to the hospital . But we must not confuse “not doing not-A ” with “wanting or doing A ”, since there is no positive exercise of will towards A. So, although initially the person was moved “like a puppet” to get into the ambulance, the person can get out at any time and, therefore, it is not determinism.

Eleonore Stump offers another analogy that may help us understand why, even though God is the ultimate and final cause of salvation in the person, the model is not deterministic. To do this, however, it is necessary to define some concepts about the volitions of human beings. “A volition is an effective desire, that is, a desire that is translated into an action if nothing external prevents it. A first-order volition is the will directing some faculty or body to do something. A second-order volition, in contrast, is a will to want something… When the will commands itself, its action is second-order . ” [66] The key that interests us here is second-order volitions. To understand this, let us imagine that someone has a first-order volition to eat meat, however, he also has the will to be a vegetarian. This would imply that it is possible for there to be conflicts between first-order volitions and second-order volitions. I suppose this is even supported biblically by the words of the apostle Paul in Romans 7:19 “For the good I want to do I do not do, but the evil I do not want to do I do.” We could say that Paul, like all human beings, has that inclination and desire to fall into temptation, but Paul, having known the truth, did not want to fall but to do what was right in the eyes of God. So his first-order desires were in conflict with his second-order desires. With this in mind, let’s look at Stump’s analogy:

“Suppose Smith wants to reform and stop smoking; he wants a will that does not want to smoke. But his second-order desire is in conflict with a very powerful first-order desire to smoke, and the conflict is usually won by that first-order desire… Now suppose there is some science-fiction device that operates on the will and that can be employed to make the will not want to smoke. For simplicity, suppose also that the device is such that Smith can put it on or take it off at any time he wants. The device operates on the will with causal efficacy but only so long as it remains attached to the person; and at any given time it is up to the person whether the device is attached or not. Let it be the case for the purposes of the example that the world is not causally determined and that the actions of Smith’s will are indeterminate in ordinary circumstances…” [67]

The question then is “is Smith’s decision to quit smoking free?” or “is Smith acting freely when he desires* not to smoke?” The answer is “Yes.” Since it is up to Smith whether the device is attached or not, it therefore meets the three conditions of libertarianism set out previously [68] . This is even if the first-order desire were irresistible and Smith were unable to generate a first-order volition not to smoke. [69]

So even if God or the device moves the person like a puppet , it is still possible to claim Libertarianism and the ambulance model is not deterministic.

Granted, I think Cross’s terminology is confusing, but if we reflect on this theory, I think it is one of the most plausible so far. If we acknowledge that the person has the capacity to resist divine movement, then the deterministic implications of the phrase “God moves the person like a puppet” begin to dissipate. For prior to A , it is possible for the person to will, choose, and perform non-A without God moving or determining him to do so. [70]

Why do some believe?

Cross acknowledges that this is a crucial point because it raises the question ‘why do some believe and others not?’, since, if we assume that God sends grace to all human beings, then the difference between the believer and the non-believer remains in the person himself.

It may be thought that the concession that a person can prevent God from producing A in her by preemptively doing not-A somehow makes her salvation dependent on her after all, since God’s doing A still depends on her not doing not-A. [71]

That is, if everything depends on whether or not the person does non-A , then salvation is still in the person’s hands. Some will say that “not doing non-A,” that is, not resisting, is a problematic notion and can be reduced to a choice on the part of the person. And so we are back to synergism. However, what is being said is not that the person should do an action but rather refrain from doing an action. That is, not resist God’s action A.

Again, Stump’s argument comes to explain this for us. Recall that what is sought is to formulate a way in which we can “hold that human beings are capable, of themselves, of rejecting grace without God being ultimately responsible for their doing so. So the will of faith [72] would be a gift from God, but it would depend on a human person whether he has such a will or not.” After examining various attempts by Augustine to try to formulate a coherent view on the matter, Stump indicates that one possible solution would be to adopt the moral psychology of Aquinas [73] , who holds that the will can assent to something or reject it , but it can also simply do nothing . [74] “If this view is right, then there are three possibilities for the will with respect to grace: the will can assent to grace, it can reject grace, or it can be quiescent to grace.” [75]

This can lead to a very interesting discussion about what could be considered a cause and what could not. I mean, if someone does not resist an action, is he performing an action? Is the absence of resistance a cause of some event? [76]

A number of philosophers agree that omissions of actions are not efficient causes of events. [77] Phil Dowe’s work can help illustrate this point [78] : if a father fails to pay attention to his son, is he to blame for his son running into the road? Our first reaction is to answer affirmatively since, if the father had paid adequate attention, then the accident would not have happened. However, the father did not cause the child to run, nor did he cause the car to speed. “What we mean is that his failure to watch his son is the cause [of the accident] in the sense that, had he watched him, the accident would not have happened… we mean that it was possible for him to have prevented the accident.” [79] Therefore, omissions are not efficient causes of events but counterfactuals of genuine causes, i.e., quasi-causes. [80]

I can still hear the determinist pressing the objection that despite the non-causality of omissions, salvation on this view is still in the hands of the person. This objection is met by an interesting distinction that Dr. Kevin Timpe makes in reflecting on this, that “omissions are quasi-causal” in the sense that they control events, but do not cause events. [81] It is said that “an agent can only be responsible for an event over which he has control” – that is, “An agent S is morally responsible for an event e only if S has (or at some point had) control over the occurrence of e.” [82] This does not deny times when a person directly causes an event or action. But Timpe tells us that we can call these cases cases of “direct control.” However, “If omissions are not causes, it is possible that genuine causation and control can be separated – an agent can control an event even if he does not actually cause it. He can control it by virtue of quasi-causing it. Let us call this ‘indirect control.’” [83] So I may have control over whether I stay in the ambulance or keep the anti-smoking device on by virtue of not getting out of the ambulance or not removing the device, but that does not mean that I caused the ride to the hospital or caused my volition not to want to smoke.

This seems to be what Dr. William Lane Craig is referring to when he says, “Our own eternal destiny is in our own hands. It is a matter of our choice where we will spend eternity.” [84] This may be considered very close to synergism, but as we have seen, it is neither synergism nor Pelagianism. By the law of identity, “close or similar to Pelagianism” does not equal “Pelagianism.” As long as we understand that God is the sufficient and only cause of saving grace and that all we can do is resist or do nothing.

So, in this proposal,

[The person] doing not-A at time t merely prevents God from producing A in her at t, so long as God does not coercively prevent her from doing not-A. This amounts to a kind of Augustinanism: damnation is, and salvation is not, something that is produced by the creature. [85]

As my friend Tim Stratton explained to me via personal message, “God is under no obligation to save anyone. There is nothing man can do to get to heaven. It is only by grace that heaven is possible.” That is, it is not that your “resistance” stops God from doing something, but rather God has sovereignly established not to do A if you do not-A , meaning God will not save you if you resist and reject His grace.

With this explained, Cross continues,

Is this view, on which a person can prevent God’s action by “getting there first,” a plausible view of resistance? It is, in the sense that not doing non-A is necessary for God to do A; and what is necessary in this case is only that the creature refrains from acting. [86]

As we mentioned above, Cross repeats it again, the question is not whether the creature performs an action, but rather “the creature refrains from performing a causal action,” in this case, an action of resistance.

While the most popular proponent of the ambulance model, Dr. Kenneth Keathley, is a Molinist, there is one Arminian who holds a very similar view. Dr. Roger Olson, in his lecture on Arminianism, draws out some distinctions between the most popular soteriological systems, in which he speaks of the Arminian model. For Dr. Olson, one of the central doctrines of Arminianism is prevenient grace [87] , which is resistible. To explain this more clearly, Olson makes use of what he calls the Wells Illustration :

“We are at the bottom of the pit in total depravity, totally incapable of doing anything. God sends a rope that represents the law, but we cannot do anything with it, we cannot use it to climb up.

But God doesn’t want to come down to save us unless we make a decision to accept Him. So He throws water into the bottom of the well and says, ‘My water will bring you up, just let My grace (water) bring you up.’

In other words, we are saved not because we did something to help (cooperate) with God’s grace. We just did not resist God’s grace. We cannot boast or be proud because we did not do anything to get out of the pit, but the water did everything to get us out” [88] .

Olson does not mention it, but if the person for whatever reason chooses not to get out of the well and swim down, he would be said to be to blame for his death at the bottom of the well. Whereas the person who gets out of the well cannot say “I pulled myself out of the well” [89] .

So it is clear that the water or ambulance representing God’s overcoming grace [90] “should and will be effective for all. The only thing that could stop it is if, inexplicably, a person decides to reject it” [91] . As Dr. Robert Picirilli puts it “[this grace] is so closely related to regeneration that it inevitably leads a person to regeneration unless resisted” [92] . Which Keathley points out is one of the benefits of the model, as it “shifts the evil of unbelief from God to the unbeliever” [93] . That is, the question is no longer “Why do some believe?” since they believe because of overcoming grace, but the question is “Why doesn’t everyone believe?” or “Why didn’t such and such a person believe?” Leaving that up to mystery to me is far better than the mystery of “deterministic predestination” that Calvinism sells us.

Meritorious Works

I want to respond to the desert objection that always arises in discussions of free will and salvation. Recall that in the first view we refuted this objection by mentioning that nothing in our actions classifies them in such a way that they “ deserve ” salvation. But still someone might still object that non-resistance is an act of the will toward grace. But again Timpe provides further reflection on this: “This objection misses the point of the view, namely, that one does not deserve credit for remaining quiescent precisely because quiescence is not a positive or good action of the will—but is a lack of an action of the will. But neither is the desire* to be quiescent with respect to divine grace something for which the agent deserves credit as long as that desire* with respect to grace is distinct from wanting* to accept grace itself…” [94] The response to the objection can be summarized thus:

  1. Nothing has been said so far that would make anything in a human being worthy of salvation.
  2. Being quiescent with respect to grace is not a causal action, it is the absence of an action, so there is no merit in an action that does not exist.
  3. Even if there is a second-degree desire or volition to be quiescent, this volition is not meritorious either because a volition to be quiescent is distinct from a volition to accept grace. [95]

My comments on the last two perspectives will not take much time, since Cross himself devotes only a paragraph in his article to both perspectives. This is because they have great similarities with some of the previously analyzed perspectives. Even so, they deserve mention and analysis.

Cross begins by explaining what one of the presuppositions was for the previous perspectives and how this presupposition will change with the next two:

So far I have assumed that the acceptance of grace consists in the completed performance of some actual or counterfactual action. Traditionally, grace and the acceptance of grace are tied to the notion of faith. Suppose, for example, that justifying grace consists, or could consist, in divinely originated faith. Since I am assuming that grace is resistible, I need such faith to be a voluntary matter. Therefore, I need to posit that faith consists in or results from some interior act of the will distinct from an exterior act—distinct from a complete performance of the act. [96]

If we recall, so far, action A , it could be any morally good action. So, according to Cross, the following views will take this action A to be having or exercising faith within a second-degree volition or interior act , if I am interpreting it correctly. But the fact that faith is divinely originated should not be ignored .

  1. INCLINATION TOWARDS FAITH

Remembering our perspective of the Supernatural Inclination ,

The relevant action is the causal result of a supernatural inclination. Such an inclination would be irresistibly given by God to a person, such that the inclination is sufficient for the action (unless it is impeded). The performance of the action counts as the acceptance of the grace.

However, in our sixth anti-Pelagian perspective,

God gives someone the inclination to an act of faith, such that such inclination is sufficient unless he is impeded from the act of faith. This view continues the same as view three, except that such inclination is for an interior act, not for the complete performance of some act. [97]

That is, while in the Supernatural Inclination the inclination is to perform an act… and if nothing intervenes, this act is produced , in the Inclination toward Faith it will be not to perform an act but to the act itself, in other words, it is not for a volition in the first degree, but is toward a volition in the second degree. Another difference is also that in (3), if person P does not want non-A then the grace of God is sufficient to produce A ( A being the complete act of salvation). Whereas in (5), we add one more step and the inclination is merely toward an act of faith and person P can refrain from exercising faith and therefore not be saved.

  1. AMBULANCE MODEL AND FAITH

This perspective correlates with the seventh so we apply the clauses of (5) in (7) with a slight distinction,

The direct action of God is sufficient unless it is impeded for the interior act of faith—as for the Anti-Pelagian strategy [seven], mutatis mutandis. [98]

Just as in the previous perspective, we merely shift the inclination or emphasis of grace from an outward act to an inward act. I don’t really see a clear distinction there. We will see this more clearly in other articles defending the plausibility and coherence of the Ambulance model.

CONCLUSION

The above views allow us to affirm a resistibility of grace and deny Pelagianism; of course, it should be noted that some are more plausible than others. However, given their variety, anyone who would argue that libertarians in denying irresistible grace affirm Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism must not only present arguments in favor of their claim, but also demonstrate that the six views presented here (and the one I present here) are inconsistent or fail in their attempt to relate the resistibility of grace and a rejection of Pelagianism.

I do not pretend to have solved a conflict that has lasted for years, a conflict that every generation deals with and will deal with until Jesus Christ returns and explains the issue to us. It is possible that all of us, Calvinists, Arminians and Molinists alike, are wrong. For now, all we can do is continue studying and delving deeper into these issues, not to debate and create conflict, but to learn more about God and glorify Him by making use of the thought He has given us.

Grades

[1] However, this ignores the fact that there are other perspectives that seek to solve the problem, such as Molinism and Open Theism. Personally, I identify myself as a Molinist and reject Open Theism as a position that undermines the Ultimate Greatness of God.

[2] The heart of the problem is not there. It is true that the presuppositions we hold influence the conclusions we reach, but the difference between Libertarians and Compatibilists is not in their view of man’s freedom, but in their view of God’s Love. Dr. Jerry Walls emphasizes this point quite well at the end of his lecture What’s Wrong with Calvinism?

[3] A specific definition of each can be found at the following link. Both Molinists and Arminians subscribe to a Soft Libertarian perspective. Calvinists subscribe to a Soft Determinism or Compatibilism perspective. Open Theists are strong libertarians.

[4] de Molina, Luis. Concord of Free Will; Dispute II. Translation Antonio Hevia Echeverría. (2007). Page 46.

[5] Dr. William Lane Craig: https://es.reasonablefaith.org/question-answer/search/el-libre-albedrio

[6] Keathley, Kenneth. Salvation & Sovereignty: A Molinist Approach . Ed. B&H Publishing Group (2010) Page 54.

[7] Stump, Eleonore. Augustine on free will . Cambridge University Press, (2006). Eleonore makes a brief survey of Augustine’s position on grace and free will. But she points out that not all philosophers agree that Libertarianism must necessarily affirm (L2). The position that affirms all three statements will be known as Common Libertarianism while the position that merely affirms (L1) and (L3) will be called Modified Libertarianism ; it is beyond the scope of this paper to argue for either proposition, the reader is free to identify with either.

[8] For a refutation of the doctrine of irresistible grace, visit the following link: “Petals Fall: Why Calvinism is Impossible.” “Petals Fall” is a series consisting of four articles that you can find here.

[9] I highly recommend reading the full article. English only.

[10] Unless otherwise indicated, these definitions will be used throughout the article.

[11] Cross, R. Anti-Pelagianism and The Resistibility of Grace , Faith and Philosophy Vol. 22. No. 2, April 2005. Page 200.

[12] Ibid. Cited by Cross.

[13] Ibid.

[14] Ibid.

[15] Ibid.

[16] Ibid. Page 199

[17] The author will use justification as a synonym for salvation, but he does not affirm any particular theory of justification. He is only interested in how justification is obtained , not in what it consists of. Nor does he adopt any theory about redemption. Nor do he adopt theories that link justification with redemption.

[18] Representation in logical symbology:

“If either Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism is true, the irresistibility of grace is false.”

(P v SP) → ¬ IG

“If either Pelagianism or Semi-Pelagianism is false, it is not necessary that the irresistibility of grace be true.”

(P v SP) → ¬(□IG)

Where:

Q: Pelagianism.

SP: Semi-Pelagianism

IG: Irresistibility of Grace.

[19] Cross, R. Anti-Pelagianism and The Resistibility of Grace, Page 199.

[20] Ibid.

[21] Ibid. Page 200

[22] Ibid. p. 201.

[23] Ibid.

[24] Ibid.

[25] Ibid. Of course, none of us would accept the idea that God is programmed to do anything. God is free to act and nothing determines or programs his actions. However, every Christian recognizes that God cannot do certain actions such as sinning and performing logical absurdities. So it is metaphysically impossible for God to break a promise.

[26] Cross, R. p. 201.

[27] Ibid.

[28] Ibid.

[29] Ibid.

[30] Ibid.

[31] http://dle.rae.es/?id=P0mceZI

[32] “Meritorious works that at most have the right to reward or honor due to equity or simple distributive justice (ex justitia distributiva), as is the case of military gratifications and decorations.” See the following link http://ec.aciprensa.com/wiki/M%C3%A9rito .

[33] Cross, R. p. 202.

[34] Ibid. p. 202.

[35] Ibid.

[36] Ibid.

[37] Ibid. p. 202.

[38] Ibid. p. 203.

[39] Ibid.

[40] Ibid.

[41] Ibid.

[42] Ibid.

[43] Ibid.

[44] Ibid.

[45] Ibid. pp. 203 – 204.

[46] Ibid. p. 204.

[47] Ibid.

[48] ​​Ibid.

[49] Ibid.

[50] Ibid.

[51] Ibid. p. 205.

[52] Ibid.

[53] Ibid.

[54] Ibid.

[55] Ibid.

[56] Ibid.

[57] Ibid.

[58] Ibid. The verb here is “to will” which has no literal translation in English. “To will” expresses an exercise of will or an inclination toward something, not merely “to want something.” The confusion arises because there are two words in English that are translated as “wanting” or “desiring,” “to want” and “to will.” The first of these is what we know as “wanting something” in the sense of having a desire for it. While the second can be specified as a volition of the agent. For simplicity, whenever I refer to “wanting” or “desiring” in the sense of an exercise of will I will add a (*) for the reader.

[59] Ibid.

[60] Ibid.

[61] Ibid. p. 206

[62] Ibid.

[63] Ibid.

[64] Ibid.

[65] Ibid. p. 207.

[66] Stump, Eleonore. Augustine on free will. Cambridge University Press, (2006), p. 126.

[67] Ibid, p. 127.

[68] Ibid, pp. 127-129.

[69] Ibid., pp. 129-130. Even if we assume that “without the device the first-order desire is irresistible,” the case still meets all three conditions of libertarianism. “Even though Smith’s will is determined by his strong desire [to smoke], he has the device available to him, and he can use it if he so chooses.” Someone might argue that if the first-order volition is irresistible, then Smith could not desire to quit smoking; it would be impossible for his second-order volition to control his first-order volition to quit smoking. But the second-order desire may be effective in doing something other than controlling his first-order desire; and that other thing may be effective at least in preventing the first-order desire from being transformed into an action (something other than using the device).

Since it is open to Smith whether to smoke or not to smoke, he satisfies (L2).

If Smith smokes, it was because he willed not to use the device and to let his desire take its course; if Smith wills not to smoke it was because he willed to use the device. So his will has been ultimately determined by his own intellect and will, and consequently has not been ultimately determined by anything outside Smith. So it satisfies (L1) and (L3).

[70] In some sense of prior, since if the creature performs non-A, there will be no act with respect to which it is prior.

[71] Cross, R. p. 206.

[72] The ‘will of faith’ or ‘will of faith’ refers to a second-order volition to have faith or to stop rejecting grace. That is, a desire of the will to want to have saving faith. This will of faith is not sufficient to will saving faith because our first-order volitions do not desire such faith. Augustine describes these second-order volitions as an acceptance of grace, a desire for a right will, a will to believe, or even merely as faith. Stump, Eleonore. Augustine on free will. Cambridge University Press, (2006), p. 136.

[73] Stump, Eleonore. Augustine on free will. Cambridge University Press, (2006), p. 126. Timpe, Kevin. Grace and Controlling what we do not Cause. Faith and Philosophy, (July 3, 2007), p. 287.

[74] Summa Theologiae Part I-IIae Question 9 – Article 1.

[75] Stump, Eleonore. Augustine on free will. Cambridge University Press, (2006), p. 140.

[76] This argument by the Reformed, “non-resistance is a cause” reminds me of the mistake that atheistic physicist Lawrence Krauss makes when he tries to argue about the universe coming into existence from nothing. (See video min. 0:52 – 1:26). “Nothing is unstable,” he tells us, “nothing will always produce something.” Sadly for Krauss and the cast of unbelievers who follow him, scholars in physics and philosophy have refuted his argument time and time again. (See video min. 6:15 onwards). When he says that the universe could have come from nothing, he is not using the word “nothing” as an ordinary person would, but rather he is referring to empty space with a physical structure, not “nothing.” Nothing, properly understood, is the absence of anything. Likewise, are we calling non-resistance a cause? If so, we would be committing the same fallacy of equivocation that Krauss commits.

[77] P Dowe, “A Counterfactual Theory of Prevention and ‘Causation’ by Omissions,” Australian Journal of Philosophy 79:2 (June 2001): 216-26; J. J. Thomson, “Causation: Omissions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66:1 (January 2003): 81-103; y S. McGrath, “Causation by Omission: A Dilemma,” Philosophical Studies 123 (2005): 125-48.”

[78] P Dowe, “A Counterfactual Theory of Prevention and ‘Causation’ by Omissions,” Australian Journal of Philosophy 79:2 (June 2001): 216-26. Del mismo autor ver también capítulo 6 de Physical Causation (Cambridge University Press, 2000).

[79] Dowe, Physical Causation, pág. 125.

[80] Aquí está el análisis de Dowe sobre la “causación por omisión”, donde A y B son eventos positivos y x es una variable que oscila entre estos eventos:

no-A cuasi-causa a B si B ocurriera y A no, y sucede una x tal que

(O1) x causó a B, y

(O2) si A hubiera ocurrido entonces A hubiera prevenido B al interactuar con x.

(Tomado de Physical Causation, pág. 124).

[81] Ver Timpe, “Controlling What We Do Not Cause,” 290-99.

[82] Ibíd, 291. Aunque esto no está afirmando que meramente “tener control” sobre un evento es suficiente para que un agente sea moralmente responsable de un evento. – ciertamente hay otras condiciones que son necesarias para la responsabilidad moral. En pocas palabras, el control es una condición necesaria pero no suficiente. El punto simplemente es que su control sobre un evento es requerido para responsabilidad moral, y hay dos maneras en la que una persona puede ejercer tal control.

[83] Ibíd.

[84] Ver: http://www.reasonablefaith.org/how-can-christ-be-the-only-way-to-god (inglés)

[85] Cross, R. pág. 206.

[86] Ibíd. pág. 207

[87] Sin embargo, en el modelo Arminiano descrito por Olson afirma que la gracia preveniente habilita al hombre depravado a responder positivamente al evangelio. Sin esa gracia preveniente, nadie sería capaz de responder al evangelio. Lo cual no refleja específicamente la intención del modelo de la ambulancia, sino que tiene mayor similitud con las perspectivas (1), (2) o (3). Pero cuando Olson describe su modelo de manera gráfica, con algunas modificaciones, parece ser que se conlleva las mismas implicaciones que el modelo de la ambulancia de Cross y Keathley.

[88] Cabe mencionar que el uso de analogías es meramente ilustrativo. Ninguna analogía es perfecta y debemos procurar entender la analogía mediante el punto que se intenta explicar.

[89] Hay claras distinciones entre el Arminianismo y el Molinismo, aspectos que van más allá de este escrito. Sin embargo, es sorprendente la similitud de las implicaciones de analogías que se usan para explicar la gracia resistible y cómo evadir la acusación de Pelagianismo.

[90] Overcoming Grace is the name Kenneth Keathly coined for the model. This would be the “O” in his acronym ROSES, for “Overcoming Grace,” which refers to a grace that overcomes our obstinacy and rebellion that we humans possess without God.

[91] Keathley, Kenneth. Salvation & Sovereignty: A Molinist Approach. Ed. B&H Publishing Group (2010), p. 77.

[92] R. Picirilli, Grace, Faith, Free Will (Nashville: Randall House 2002), 156. Emphasis added.

[93] Keathley, K. p. 77.

[94] Timpe, “Controlling What We Do Not Cause,” Reference (49) 298.

[95] Still, the reformed will press the point, saying, “But it is better not to resist than to resist, therefore the person may boast.” But Timpe reminds us that superlatives do not presuppose positives. That is, just because something is better than something else does not imply that the former is a positive thing to boast about. For example, suppose Joe has the opportunity to steal $100 from his boss, but only steals $20. Joe’s action is better than it would have been, but it does not mean that Joe deserves any moral merit for the action he did take.

[96] Cross, R. p. 207.

[97] Ibid. p. 207-208.

[98] Ibid. p. 208 Cross comments that it is not necessary to define saving faith precisely for the purposes of his analysis. Since faith is intended to be a voluntary act, faith is viewed as a trust in the offer of salvation and in the Savior, rather than as a belief in certain propositions.

 


Raúl Jaramillo is a graduate in Telecommunications Engineering from the Autonomous University of San Luis Potosí. Certified by the Reasonable Faith ministry as an apologetics teacher and leader of a study group or chapter of the ministry. Guest writer on Chris Du Pond’s blog veritasfidei.org , founding member of the Christian Philosopher ministry . Raúl has dedicated the last 10 years to promote the distribution of apologetic material in Spanish supporting Reasonable Faith with articles, conferences and debates; and Free Thinking Ministries with weekly articles. He has held debates on free will from a Molinist worldview making a strong criticism of Calvinist determinism. He is currently the Regional Director of Reasonable Faith Chapters for Latin America and Spain.