By William Lane Craig
SUMMARY
Whether God is timeless or temporal depends on whether an A-Theory or a B-Theory of time is correct, where the former presents temporal facts and the latter only timeless facts. Given the superiority of the A-Theory, it follows that God is temporal. But since the Special Theory of Relativity relativizes simultaneity to reference frames, the question arises of what “now” is God’s “now.” To answer that question, we must distinguish between time and our measurements of time. Relativity concerns only measured time and therefore does not affect God’s actual time. How does God’s time relate to measured time? Contra Alan Padgett, God’s time must coincide with a measured time, most plausibly the cosmic time of the General Theory of Relativity.
Introduction
While some of the traditional attributes of God, such as omnipotence or omniscience (particularly divine foreknowledge) have been exhaustively—and one is tempted to say almost exhaustively—analyzed and defended in recent philosophical literature, other divine attributes such as the eternity of God have received scant and generally superficial analysis. [1] Current discussions of the eternity of God have for the most part been conducted in almost complete ignorance of the philosophy of space and time and without any deep knowledge of the theory of relativity and its analysis of time [2] —a notable deficiency, when one thinks about it, for how can one hope to formulate an adequate doctrine of the eternity of God and its relation to time without taking into account what modern philosophy and science have to say about time?
Now Alan Padgett, a PhD candidate under Richard Swinburne, has attempted to remedy that lack by presenting, in full conversation with philosophical and scientific discussions of time, a view of divine eternity that he characterizes as “relative timelessness.” [3] As someone who has recently been working in this very area, I wish to endorse the direction in which Padgett is moving and offer some refinements to this view.
The Eternal Eternity of God: Theory A vs. Theory B of Time
Padgett rejects the classical Plotinian-Augustinian analysis of divine eternity in terms of timeless existence, a view he calls “absolute timelessness.” He regards the classical analysis as inadequate because God, in order to sustain created things, which are always changing in their ontological state, must change in his activity and therefore cannot be timeless.
What Padgett’s article does not make clear, however, is that this line of argument only carries through if one has previously committed oneself to an A-theory of time. [4] According to the A-theorist, temporal becoming is a real, objective feature of the universe; transience is essential to the nature of time, a truth expressed metaphorically by saying that time “flows.” The temporal properties of events cannot be adequately analyzed in terms of prior , simultaneous , and posterior alone, but must include references to the past , present , and future , which are not merely deictic expressions but are irreducibly temporal. The present represents the edge of becoming, and future events merely do not exist yet , but do not exist at all . By contrast, according to the B-theorist, temporal becoming is mind-dependent and purely subjective. Time does not flow, nor do things come into being, except in the sense that at one moment we are aware of them after not having been at an earlier moment. Simultaneous things with different moments on the timeline are equally existent and interrelated to each other by the prior, simultaneous and subsequent relationships to which past, present and future can be reduced. Anything that, from our perspective, existed, exists or will exist in the universe, simply exists (without temporality).
By contrast, on the A-theory of time, the concept of a timeless God who is actually related to the world seems incoherent. Since future states of the universe do not actually exist, God cannot be causing them (even timelessly) to exist; otherwise, they would in fact exist at their respective times. The same holds for past states of the universe. Thus, Aquinas’s argument that God causes timeless things to happen at their respective times only succeeds in showing that things caused by time need not exist eternally, and in fact betrays a B-theoretic view. [5] Even if God immutably wills from eternity that a temporal event exist, there must be attached to that will an exercise of divine causality at the time of the thing’s creation for it to actually happen at that time rather than existing timelessly at that time. The only way to avoid this conclusion would be to deny with Aquinas that God is really related to the world, a totally implausible system of motion that depends on an elaborate Aristotelian metaphysics. [6]
It can be plausibly argued, I think, that the A-theory of time is philosophically and theologically superior to the B-theory. Philosophically, one should agree with D. H. Mellor that “time is such a striking aspect of reality that only the most compelling argument justifies denying it: namely, that the dynamical view of time is contradictory and therefore cannot be true” [7] and then proceed to show that in fact all such attempts to provoke a contradiction, such as McTaggart’s, fail, [8] leaving us secure in our naturally intuitive understanding of the A-theory. No B-theorist, on the other hand, has successfully answered, in my view, the charge that his theory is incoherent because mental dependence on physical becoming requires real becoming in the subjective contents of consciousness. [9] In favor of theory A, one could argue that it offers the most adequate analysis of personal identity [10] and that the temporality of our language and experience is inescapable. [11]
Theologically, there seems to be one decisive reason for Christian theists to reject the B-theory, namely, that it cannot give an adequate analysis of the biblical doctrine of creatio ex nihilo . In the B-theory, creatio ex nihilo is reduced to the ontological dependence of creation on God and the space-time continuum with an edge or boundary. But creation as a whole is co-eternal with God in the sense that it exists as timelessly as He does. There is no state of affairs in the present world that consists in God existing alone without creation. But such an analysis is a wholly inadequate understanding of the biblical doctrine that the created order came into existence and was created by God. Although Aquinas (unlike Bonaventure) thought that one could not philosophically prove this aspect of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo , he was firmly committed to it on the basis of revelation, a fact that contemporary theologians, who sometimes appeal to Aquinas to justify their undue reliance on temporal creativity ex nihilo , tend to forget. [12]
Padgett’s argument against divine timelessness, then, is valid only if the case for an A-theory is successful. What the reader of Padgett’s paper will not realize is that Padgett himself is fully aware of this point and argues for the superiority of the A-theory in his unpublished thesis. On this point, therefore, we are in fundamental agreement.
God’s time and ours
If the A-theory of time is correct, then, and God is in time, the question naturally arises in the context of the theory of relativity: “Whose time is God in?” According to that theory, events that are present to an observer in one inertial frame may be future to an observer in another inertial frame. Certain events will even occur in reverse temporal order relative to some frames compared to others. An observer at rest relative to an observer making a high-speed round trip will experience moments of time or “nows” for which there literally are no correlated simultaneous moments in the traveler’s experience. According to Einstein, neither of these perspectives is privileged, and therefore there is no absolute “now” in the universe. Absolute simultaneity has been banished from the universe in favor of simultaneity relative to a frame of reference. For example, no event occurs “now” in an absolute sense on the planet Neptune or even on the other side of the earth. For observers in relatively mobile reference frames, at this same space-time point they will draw different planes of simultaneity in space-time and thus measure different events, say, on Neptune, as occurring in their respective “nows.” But what is God’s “now”?
Ontological time and measured time
It is to the credit of Padgett’s work that he has cut this Gordian knot by distinguishing between “time” and “measured time.” [13] Time itself, according to Padgett, has to do with God’s eternal duration; measured time is clock time, time according to some metric. Padgett argues that while God is in time, he is not in any measured time, and therefore his “now” is not to be identified with any of the relative “nows” of measured time.
This distinction between ontological time and measured (or empirical) time seems to me to be an extremely important insight, which is a healthy counterweight to the universally repeated and extravagant claims that TRE has forced us to abandon: the classical views of time and space. [14] This erroneous inference rests precisely on the failure to draw the kind of distinction that Padgett has emphasized. That failure can be laid at Einstein’s door. It seems astonishing to me that anyone reading Einstein’s 1905 paper could think that Einstein proved that there is no absolute simultaneity, and that therefore time is relative to reference frames. [15] For the whole theory depends on the acceptance of Einstein’s arbitrary (and, indeed, highly counterintuitive) definition of simultaneity, [16] together with a philosophical positivism of Machian provenance [17] according to which a notion like absolute simultaneity is meaningless if it is empirically undetectable. Since the ether frame of 19th century physics could not be detected empirically, Einstein dismissed it as meaningless, along with his absolute simultaneity, which referred to events occurring simultaneously in the ether frame. By redefining simultaneity in terms of the light signal timing method, Einstein was able to give empirical meaning to the notion of simultaneity, but the simultaneity that emerges from the theory is relative due to the invariant speed of light. Since light signals are measured as having the speed c regardless of the motion of the sender or receiver of the signals, two relatively moving observers will measure the same event occurring at different times, which goes against the traditional notion of simultaneity. [18]
Anyone who is not a positivist, and therefore rejects Einstein’s definitions, would regard these relatively soulful observers as deluded because of the nature of their measurements, which cannot detect real time. [19] In a real sense, he would not regard Einstein’s theory as a theory about time and space at all, but, as Frank put it, as “a system of hypotheses about the behavior of light rays, rigid bodies, and mechanisms, from which new results about this behavior can be derived.” [20] Trapped in our locally moving frames, we may be forced to measure time by devices that are inadequate to detect real time, but that by no means implies that there is no such time. The fact that uniformly moving clocks run slowly says more about our clocks than about the nature of time. Thus, Einstein’s theory can be regarded as pragmatically useful and scientifically fruitful without having to regard absolute simultaneity and absolute time as abolished.
One might think that Einstein’s positivism was simply a historically accidental feature of the theory, but it is not part of the philosophical foundations of that theory. Such an attitude, however, would be mistaken. As J.S. Bell points out, it is primarily this philosophical positivism that serves to distinguish the Einsteinian interpretation of lavTRE from the Lorentzian interpretation, which differentiates between ontological time and measured time:
The difference in philosophy is this. Since it is experimentally impossible to tell which of two systems of uniform motion is really at rest, Einstein declares that the notions of “really at rest” and “really in motion” are meaningless. For him, only the relative motion of two or more objects in uniform motion is real. Lorentz, on the other hand, preferred to see that there does indeed exist a real state of rest, defined by the “ether,” even though the laws of physics conspire to prevent us from identifying it experimentally. The facts of physics do not force us to accept one philosophy rather than the other. [21]
Since the Lorentzian interpretation of the TER is empirically equivalent to Einstein’s interpretation, the only way the latter can rule out the former is by a positivist critique of notions of absolute simultaneity, and so on. According to Lawrence Sklar,
“Certainly the original arguments for the relativist view are riddled with verificationist presuppositions about meaning, etc. And despite Einstein’s later denial of the verificationist view, no one to my knowledge has provided an adequate account of the foundations of relativity that is not verificationist in essence.” [22] “I see no way to reject the old compensatory ether theories […] without invoking a verificationist criticism of one sort or another.” [23]
Now this constitutes a truly serious drawback of Einstein’s interpretation. As Healey observes, although positivists tried to restrict the content of scientific theories in order to ensure that they were meaningful, “more recently positivism has come under such sustained attack that opposition has become almost orthodoxy in the philosophy of science.” [24] Philosophers of religion need not be reminded of the untenability of positivism in view of their radical critique of religious language, which would regard Padgett’s distinction between God’s time and our time as cognitively meaningless.
Since God is in time, therefore, it is evident that His is not the time that is determined by Einstein’s operational definitions; subject to dilation, the relativity of simultaneity, and the reversal of events. Rather, God’s time is true A-series time, determined by the succession of events in divine consciousness and activity and characterized by the absolute “now” of the present and the edge of becoming. His is, to borrow D.H. Mellor’s phrase, “Real Temporality.”
So I think it’s rather unfortunate that Padgett chose to call his view “relative timelessness,” because it is precisely the opposite. It is God who exists in true ontological time, while finite observers, restricted to our locally moving reference frames dependent on the light signal timing of clocks, have to make do with our manufactured measured time. Contrary to Padgett, ordinary use of time concepts cannot justify calling God relatively timeless, since our intuitive view of time is an A-theoretic view, and this is precisely the time in which God lives. Thus, the view Padgett presents is better labeled “Real Temporality.”
God’s time and cosmic time
But how does God’s time relate to our own? Padgett answers that while we are in God’s time, God is not in any measured time. But this answer seems to me to be factually false. From the perspective of God in the real time of the A-series, there is an absolute present in which he is now aware of what is happening in the universe, and he is now causally causing the events in the universe. But if, as we saw in our critique of divine timelessness, God’s causally sustaining the universe in being is simultaneous with the events being sustained, then there must be an absolute cosmic “now” that describes the state of the universe as it is present to God. Future events for this moment do not exist at all, since God has not yet caused them. But is there a frame of reference in the universe that produces a measured time that can be naturally associated with the succession of such moments? Yes, there is. It is not, in fact, the inertial frame of any spatially local observer, but the reference frame of the cosmic expansion of space itself. The relativity of simultaneity depends on the assumption that there is no preferred reference frame; but if there is a preferred frame, as the Lorentzian interpretation would have it, then the relations of simultaneity in it would be absolute, and relativity would apply to all other frames. But the frame associated with cosmic expansion seems naturally suited to such a privileged position. Michael Shallis explains:
However, it is also possible to take a single clock as a standard, to define a universal time coordinate and to relativize everything to it […] Of course, the choice of a coordinate time is to some extent arbitrary; in principle, one could take any clock as a standard. But in a cosmological context, it is natural to take as a standard a clock whose motion is typical or representative of the motion of matter in general, one that simply “advances,” so to speak, with the general expansion of the universe. [25]
We must not forget that Einstein proposed his Special Theory long before cosmic expansion was discovered, so that in the absence of the characterless and dying ether, there seemed to be no empirical basis for positing any universal frame beyond the multitude of locally moving frames. But with the discovery that the universe is expanding, it became possible to imagine a universal frame of reference by imagining observers associated with fundamental particles (i.e., galaxies or galaxy clusters) having mutual recessional velocities. In fact, the “gas” constituted by these fundamental particles is at rest relative to the expansion of cosmic space and is therefore an ether. As early as 1920, Eddington acknowledged that the General Theory of Relativity postulated a kind of cosmic time, but he objected that such cosmic time was unknowable and therefore irrelevant to observers in moving local frames. [26] Within a few years, however, the expansion of the universe predicted by Einstein’s field equations (minus the cosmological constant) had been confirmed by observational astronomy, thus providing a sort of cosmic clock that the abandonment of the aether theory seemed to have served no practical purpose. Of course, it might still be objected that this universal time is unknowable and therefore irrelevant. But not only does this objection seem to be infected with a defunct verificationist attitude, it does not even seem to be true. Recent observations have revealed an apparent anisotropy in the cosmic microwave background radiation that is due to the motion of the earth relative to the cosmic reference frame, resulting in what has been characterized as a “new aether wind” of about 360 kilometers per second. [27] Comments by P.C. W. Davies,
At any given location in the universe, there is only one reference frame in which the universe is expanding isotropically. This privileged reference frame defines a privileged time scale (the time indicated by a clock at rest in that frame). Two separate locations have their privileged reference frames in mutual motion, due to the expansion of the universe. However, the time measured by the entire collection of imaginary standard clocks is obviously correlated such that the global condition (e.g., the average separation of two galaxies) of the universe appears the same at times equal to those recorded by each privileged clock (assuming they are all correctly synchronized). Fortunately, the Earth moves very slowly relative to the local privileged frame in our vicinity of the universe, so Earth time is a fairly accurate measure of cosmic time. [28]
Not only, then, is there cosmic time, but we even have a pretty good idea of what time it is.
Given the existence of this cosmic time, I believe that the moments of God’s actual time, the A-series—while perhaps not identical to the moments of measured cosmic time—do coincide. God’s ontological time clearly exceeds the cosmic time by which the former could have preceded the latter (imagine God leading creation by counting “1, 2, 3, … fiat lux !”), but once cosmic time comes into existence, its moments would coincide with the moments of actual time. How could they fail to do so? If the duration of the universe is measured in cosmic time at 15 billion years from the singularity, isn’t the duration of God’s creative activity in actual time the same duration? In God’s “now” the universe has (present time) certain specific and unique properties, for example, a certain radius, a certain density, a certain background temperature, etc., but in the cosmic “now” it has all the identical properties, and so it is with each successive “now.” Is it not obvious that these “nows” coincide and designate the same present?
Perhaps we can state this consideration more formally by the following principle:
P : For any recurrent, constantly changing universe U and time intervals x , y large enough to allow change, if the physical description of U at x is the same as the physical description of U at y , then x and y coincide.
Since in real time there is a temporal interval or duration during which a certain physical description of the universe is true, and since in cosmic time there is a similar interval, it follows from P that those intervals of real and cosmic time coincide. Note that the argument makes no reference to any particular metrication of time and therefore does not depend on it. It seems to me, then, that real time and cosmic time should naturally be regarded as coinciding since the beginning of cosmic time.
Padgett’s objections to this understanding of the relationship of God’s time to measured time appear to be rather weak. He first objects that God is not subject to the laws of nature, as anything in measured time must be. He argues that since God acts freely rather than uniformly and has the power to alter the laws of nature, he cannot be in measured time. But why could not God’s time contain its own intrinsic metric, as Newton believed, that physical clocks provide a more or less “sensible” measure? [29] In this case, an ideal physical clock would measure God’s time. Furthermore, the premise that anything in measured time must be subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur. It is the measuring instrument , i.e. the clock , that must be subject to the laws of nature, not the object of measurement, which could be a totally random process. To say that 15 billion years ago God created the universe is not to say that God is subject to the laws of planetary motion, but simply to apply to God’s time a conventional metric that marks a duration equal to the duration of the earth’s orbit around the sun. That is to say that the duration during which God thought or did something is equal to, say, the duration it would take the earth to complete a certain number of orbits. Even on a purely mundane level, global proper time near the singularity is not a direct count of simple, real phenomena, since the earth will not have actually completed, say, 1010 orbits in the last 1010 years and even a cesium atomic clock would not have ticked at very early intervals. Rather, global proper time is an elaborate mathematical extrapolation of physical phenomena. [30] Similarly, any arbitrarily chosen metric can be applied to the duration of God or the universe.
Padgett anticipates such an objection, supposing that the universe might be thought of as acting as a kind of clock to measure the length of God’s time. But let’s be quite clear about this, for the universe does not merely act as a clock for God. The universe is a clock; it is God’s clock. For example, some conventional unit of God’s time might be the time it takes for the radius of the universe to increase by a certain factor. Padgett retorts that it does not follow that because two events e1 and e2 are one hour apart in one frame of reference, they are one hour apart in God’s time. He appeals to time dilation between relatively moving frames to show that the duration between two identical events can be measured diversely. But the analogy fails here, for we are not comparing two relatively moving frames using light signals to synchronize their respective clocks. Since God is actually related to the universe and not moving relative to it, there is no basis for any relativity of simultaneity between His present and the cosmic present. God is a disembodied Mind that uses a physical clock.
Padgett objects that cosmic time is contingent and applies only to our universe. We cannot, therefore, suppose that it applies to anything beyond it. But we have no reason, biblical or philosophical, to think that there are other universes. Parsimony justifies the assumption that ours is the only universe. In that case, it only follows that actual time and cosmic time contingently coincide ; there are possible worlds in which they do not. [31] But why is that an objection? Since God’s decision to create was free, cosmic time is essentially contingent; indeed, I should say that even actual time is contingent. [32] But since cosmic time exists, there is no objection to holding that God’s time contingently coincides with it for the duration of the cosmos.
Padgett’s second objection to this view is that measured time is relative to a particular frame of reference, which need not apply to God. He argues that because God transcends space, his life need not occur in our four-dimensional space-time continuum. Therefore, his life is not limited to the temporal dimension of our space-time.
This objection raises some interesting questions about divine omnipresence, [33] which we can give up. One might also question whether the objection has sufficient insight into the difference between parameter time and coordinate time. [34] In Newtonian mechanics, time functions as a parameter, which is entirely independent of space. However, in the theory of relativity, time functions not only as a parameter, but also as a coordinate that is joined with spatial coordinates. However, that theory is susceptible to reformulation entirely in terms of parameter time. One might therefore argue that God is in measured time, but that means therefore parameter time, not coordinate time, so that God’s independence from space is preserved. However, the essential point to be made is that God’s time can be measured by coordinate time without His being also measured by spatial coordinates, because on the understanding I have proposed, moments of ontological time can be thought of as coinciding with moments of measured time without being identical to them. Thus, even if it is true that a being whose duration is measured exclusively by coordinate time must also have spatial coordinates, it does not follow that a being whose duration in ontological time coincides with its duration in measured time must also be in space. Again, the fact that this coincidence is contingent constitutes no objection, but it is in fact implied by traditional theism.
It seems to me, therefore, that Padgett’s view needs to be refined with respect to the relationship between ontological time and measured time, and hence between God’s time and our own. Real time is the time of the A-series in which God thinks and acts and in which things come into being; the moments of this time coincide from the beginning of the universe with the moments of cosmic time determined by ideal stationary clocks with respect to the expansion of space itself.
Conclusion
I believe, therefore, that Padgett has gone a long way toward formulating a philosophically sound and scientifically informed doctrine of divine eternity that is also faithful to biblical revelation. The philosophical and theological grounds for preferring an A-theory of time also provide justification for rejecting the Plotine-Augustinian doctrine of divine timelessness because that theory seems incompatible with the real relationship of a timeless God to the world. God thinks and acts in real time—that is, the A-series of temporal moments, in which becoming, absolute simultaneity, and absolute “now” exist—and his relationship to time must be characterized as “true temporality.” In contrast, by conventionally defining simultaneity in terms of the light-signal method of clock synchronization and by adopting arbitrary metrics to quantify time, men have developed a measured time, which is extremely malleable to relatively moving timekeepers. Since God is not in any inertial frame, his time, ontological time, is not subject to these effects. However, in our universe, due to its isotropic expansion from an initial singularity, there is cosmic time that records successive moments in the history of the universe. Although ontological time may precede (or succeed) measured cosmic time—whether ontological time has a beginning is an issue we have not sought to judge in this article—nevertheless, the moments of ontological time and cosmic time will coincide for the duration of cosmic time, since they refer to the identical succession of states in the universe. To object that this makes God subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur , since it is our clocks that must be subject. To object that this view traps God in spacetime is equally mistaken, since ontological time only contingently coincides with cosmic time, so that God in ontological time can exist at a time that coincides with a measured moment of time without having to possess coordinate space as well. One of the interesting implications of this understanding is that a Lorentzian rather than an Einsteinian interpretation of the special theory of relativity is correct: there is a preferred reference frame in which light propagates with speed c , and relativistic effects are due to local motion relative to this frame. With these refinements, Padgett’s view of divine eternity appears to be coherent and plausible.
Grades
[1] Note that the literature on divine eternity is so sparse that it did not even merit a mention in Philosophy of Religion: an Annotated Bibliography of Twentieth Century Writings in English (New York: Garland Publishing, 1978).
[2] See, for example. Nelson Pike, God and Timelessness (New York: Schocken Books, 1970); Stephen T. Davis, Logic and the Nature of God (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1983); Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “Eternity,” Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981):429-58.
[3] Alan Padgett, “God and Time: Toward a New Doctrine of Divine Timeless Eternity,” Religious Studies 25 (1989): 209-15); see further idem , “Divine Eternity and the Nature of Time” (Ph.D. thesis, Oxford University, 1988) [now published as God, Eternity, and the Nature of Time (New York: St. Martin’s, 1992)].
[4] The distinction between the A and B series of temporal events was originally made by J. M. E. McTaggart, The Nature of Existence , 2 vols., ed. C. D. Broad (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927; rep. ed.: 1968), Book V, chs. 33; for discussion, see C. D. Broad, Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy , 2 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1938; rep. ed.: New York: Octagon Books, 1976), 2:265–344. See also Richard Gale, “Introduction” to Section II: “The Static versus the Dynamic Temporal,” in The Philosophy of Time , ed. R. Gale (London: Macmillan, 1968), pp. 65–85.
[5] On the connection between classical conceptions of divine eternity and a B theory of time, see Wm. L. Craig, The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez , Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 7 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1988), pp. 116–21; idem, “St. Anselm on Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingency,” Laval théologique et philosophique 42 (1986):93–104. See also Delmas Lewis, “Eternity, Time and Tenselessness,” Faith and Philosophy 5 (1988):72–86.
[6] For a brief critique, see Wm. L. Craig, “God, Time, and Eternity,” Religious Studies 14 (1979):497-503.
[7] D.H. Mellor, Real Time (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 5.
[8] See refutation in Paul Horwich, Asymmetries in Time (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 26–27. Horwich’s own rejection of A-theory is based on the mistaken view that an A-theory entails the denial of semantic bivalence for contingent future propositions.
[9] Such an objection needs to be formulated more carefully, but is detailed in Milic Capek, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics (Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1961), p. 165; idem, “Introduction,” in The Concepts of Space and Time , ed. M. Capek, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), p. XLVII; Frederick Ferré, “Grünbaum on Temporal Becoming: A Critique,” International Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1972):432-33; James A. McGilvray, “A Defense of Physical Becoming,” Erkenntnis 14 (1979):275-99.
[10] See Ronald C. Hoy, “Becoming and Persons,” Philosophical Studies 34 (1978):269-80.
[11] See Quentin Smith, “Problems with the New Tenseless Theory of Time,” Philosophical Studies 52 (1987):371-92 and the literature cited therein.
[12] See, for example, John Polkinghorne, “Cosmology and Creation,” paper presented at the conference “The Origin of the Universe,” Colorado State University, Ft. Collins, Colorado, September 22-25, 1988. The proceedings will probably be published by SUNY Press.
[13] This much-misunderstood distinction was carefully worked out by Newton himself in the Scholium to the Definitions at the beginning of his Principia (Isaac Newton, Sir Isaac Newton’s ‘Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy’ and his ‘System of the World’, trans. Andrew Motte, rev. with appendix by Florian Cajori, 2 vols. [Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1966], pp. 6–12). Cf. M. F. Cleugh, Time and its Importance in Modern Thought (London: Methuen, 1937), pp. 29–67; Philipp Frank, Philosophy of Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1957), pp. 140–43; Herbert Dingle, “Time in Philosophy and Physics,” Philosophy 54 (1979):99–104.
[14] Typical are Hawking’s recent statements: “…the theory of relativity puts an end to the idea of absolute time […] The theory of relativity forces us to fundamentally change our ideas of space and time.” (Stephen Hawking, A Brief History of Time [New York: Bantam Books, 1988], pp. 21, 23).
[15] A. Einstein, “On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies,” in The Principle of Relativity , trans. W. Perrett and GB Jeffery with notes by A. Sommerfield (New York: Dover Publications, 1952), pp. 37-65.
[16] Two spatially separated events are simultaneous if they both occur at the same clock hours as recorded by two synchronized clocks A and B situated respectively at the locations of the events, where A and B are stationary relative to each other and B reads the same as A at the temporal midpoint of the time required for A to send a light signal to B and receive it back. The assumption is that A and B are not moving with reference to the ether-frame, so the travel time of the signal is no longer (or shorter) on the return leg of its journey. Now, clearly, unless one is an operationalist, this is not what is meant by simultaneity, and unless one is a positivist, the underlying assumption of the definition is entirely gratuitous.
[17] The influence of Mach’s positivism on Einstein and his Special Theory of Relativity is widely acknowledged by historians of science, but surprisingly rarely discussed by philosophers exploring the philosophical foundations of that theory. For discussion, see G. Holton, “Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality,” in Ernst Mach: Physicist and Philosopher , Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1970), pp. 167-77; P. Frank, “Einstein, Mach, and Logical Positivism,” in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P. A. Schilpp, Library of Living Philosophers 7 (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1949), pp. 271-86; H. Reichenbach, “The Philosophical Significance of the Theory of Relativity”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 289-311.
[18] For alternative operational definitions of “simultaneity” and “synchronization” that preserve absolute simultaneity, see T. Sjödin, “On the One-Way Velocity of Light and its Possible Measurability”, paper presented at the conference Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory , British Society for the Philosophy of Science, Imperial College, London, September 16–19, 1988.
[19] This is, in fact, the modern Lorentzian interpretation of SRT, which holds that velocity affects our measuring devices, so that moving rods and clocks contract slowly. Such an interpretation does not commit us to a substantive ether, but merely to an ether- frame , i.e. a privileged frame of reference. The fact that the Lorentzian interprets longitudinal contraction and time dilation as not merely apparent but real cannot be cited as a disadvantage of the theory, since the Einsteinian must also postulate real contraction and dilation (see Peter Kroes’ paper “The Physical Status of Time Dilation within the Special Theory of Relativity,” at the conference mentioned in note 18; see also Dennis Dieks, “The `Reality’ of the Lorentz Contraction,” Zeitschrift fur allgemeine Wissenschafts-theorie 15/2). The difference between the two on this point is that the Lorentzian offers some explanation for these effects, while the Einsteinian does not. The decision between a Lorentzian and an Einsteinian interpretation of SRT will probably depend on whether God’s time can plausibly be interpreted to coincide with some coordinate time, which would therefore be the privileged time of the aether frame.
[20] Frank, Philosophy of Science , p. 140.
[21] J. S. Bell, “How to Teach Special Relativity,” in Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics , ed. JS Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 77.
[22] Lawrence Sklar, “Time, reality and relativity,” in Reduction, Time and Reality , ed. R. Healey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 141.
[23] Ibid., p. 132
[24] R. Healey, “Introduction,” in Reduction, Time and Reality , p. vii.
[25] Muchael Shallis, “Time and Cosmology,” in The Nature of Time , ed. Raymond Flood and Michael Lockwood (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp. 68-69.
[26] Arthur Eddington, Space, Time and Gravitation , Cambridge Science Classics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 168:
In the first place, absolute space and time are restored for cosmic-scale phenomena […] The world taken as a whole has a direction in which it does not curve; that direction gives a kind of absolute time distinct from space. Relativity is reduced to local phenomena; and although this is sufficient for the theory so far described, we are inclined to look at the limitation reluctantly. But we have already insisted that the theory of relativity is not concerned with denying the possibility of absolute time, but with denying that it is concerned with any experimental knowledge that has been found; and we need not be disturbed if the conception of absolute time appears in a new form in a theory of cosmic-scale phenomena, of which no experimental knowledge is yet available.
[27] GF Smoot, MV Gorenstein, and RA Muller, “Detection of Anisotropy in the Cosmic Blackbody Radiation,” Physical Review Letters 39 (1977): 899.
[28] PCW Davies, “Space-Time Singularities in Cosmology and Black Hole Evaporations,” in The Study of Time III , ed. JT Fraser, N. Lawrence, and D. Park (Berlin: Springer Verlag, 1978), p. 76. I have corrected spelling errors in the quote.
[29] See Charles W. Misner, Kip S. Thorne, John A. Wheeler, Gravitation (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1973), pp. 813-14. The authors’ attempt to criticize proper global time as inadequately physical fails to appreciate the counterfactual nature of the application of the metric; elapsed time is measured as if an atomic clock were present and running.
[30] For a helpful discussion see Peter Kroes, Time: Its Structure and Its Role in Physical Theories , Synthese Library 179 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), p. 49.
[31] By postulating a cosmic rotation of matter, Gödel was able to work out model universes satisfying Einstein’s field equations in which there is no cosmic time (Kurt Gödel, “A Remark about the Relationship between Relativity Theory and Idealistic Philosophy”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 557–62). In such worlds, Padgett’s view would be correct. But in fact, there is cosmic time, and it naturally appears to coincide with real time.
[32] See my “God, Time and Eternity,” pp. 497-503, where I argue that God existing without creation is timeless and that He enters time at its beginning with His creation of the universe. Since creation is a freely willed act of God, the existence of actual time is therefore contingent.
[33] See, for example, Eddington’s observation:
Just as each limited observer has his own particular separation of space and time, so a being coextensive with the world might well have a special separation of space and time natural to him. It is the moment of this being which is here dignified by the title of “absolute.” (Eddington, Space, Time and Gravitation , p. 168)
[34] See Kroes, Time , pp. 60-96.
William Lane Craig is an American Baptist Christian analytic philosopher and theologian. Craig’s philosophical work focuses on the philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and philosophy of time. His theological interests lie in historical Jesus studies and philosophical theology.
Original Blog: http://bit.ly/3aWccf2
Translated by Jairo Izquierdo
Are Pro-Lifers Who Own Guns Hypocrites?
Legislating Morality, Culture & PoliticsBy Nathan Apodaca
Another assertion has become commonplace in discussions of abortion. Pro-lifers who own firearms, or support military actions abroad are misled at best, and at worst, hypocrites. The critic assumes that any inconsistently held pro-life beliefs are evidence pro-lifers aren’t actually motivated by a desire to protect human life, but rather a desire to control women’s liberty. This line of criticism lacks substance and misunderstands both the essential pro-life position as well as why people support gun rights or particular military actions.
Suppose for a moment it’s true that the vast majority of pro-lifers are hypocritical in how they hold their views on protecting life across various issues. Would that supposition invalidate the pro-life position as a whole? The essential pro-life argument is as follows:
If the premises are true (and there’s good reason to believe they are) and the conclusion logically follows, then the argument is sound. Would a subset of the pro-life community being hypocrites demonstrate that either premise is untrue? Of course not. Neither the wrongness of killing innocent human beings nor the nature of abortion and its victims are in any way impacted by whether some pro-life advocates behave inconsistently toward life in regards to the views they champion.
In fact, this is little more than a personal attack. It’s highly unlikely that if the moral consistency of particular pro-lifers changed overnight, these critics would then drop their support for abortion. It’s a smokescreen, an attempt to poison the well of the pro-life cause, not an actual rebuttal of the above argument.
Guns Protect Life
That being said, the claim that supporting gun rights or military service is inconsistent with the pro-life view is mistaken. As philosopher Tim Hsaio points out, self-defense is an extension of the right to life, intrinsic to all human beings. Since all human beings have the natural (intrinsic or God-given) right to life, then it is perfectly just for human beings to take steps to prevent themselves from being victimized by those with an evil intent. Writes Hsaio,
Remember, the reason abortion is wrong is because it intentionally kills an innocent human being. The vast majority of Americans who purchase firearms do not do so for the purpose of going out and intentionally killing innocent human beings, but for self-defense purposes or for protecting friends and family from those with wicked intentions.
What About Military Service?
Military action is a bit more complicated but still serves as a further extension of this principle. Being a service-member myself (Going on six years as a Cavalry Scout in the Army National Guard) I have received the question on numerous occasions, why do I oppose abortion if I am engaged in a line of work where my job is predicated upon the taking of human life?
The question ultimately relies on a confusion of moral principles. Remember, pro-lifers oppose elective abortion because it intentionally takes the life of innocent human beings. We could be mistaken in that claim, but that doesn’t necessarily make us inconsistent if we support or serve in the Armed Forces. It’s impossible to find a valid comparison between an ISIS fighter or a Nazi executioner and an unborn child. It’s not even worth pondering.
The ethics of warfare are complex and involve a great amount of moral ambiguity, but at their core are the same basic principles which underlie both the pro-life position and self-defense. Just as a toddler cannot adequately exercise the ability to defend their life or well-being, and therefore needs an adult (such as a parent) to fill this role, governments must protect the lives of citizens against immoral aggressors such as foreign states and terror groups. This is why we have police, intelligence services, and the military provided by civil government.
Debates over the ethics of contemporary military actions abroad usually come down to finer details about how to effectively engage enemy combatants and achieve victory with minimal loss of innocent life. While a military commander may foresee the loss of life on the battlefield, this in no way makes a conflict inherently immoral, provided steps are taken to mitigate the loss of life without compromising the overall mission. For instance, the introduction of laser-guided weaponry, thermal imaging, communications, and better surveillance/reconnaissance equipment has been a major boon towards limiting the risk to civilians(and friendly forces) caught in the crossfire of a battle.[2]
Even when an attack or war is being fought for justified reasons, the loss of innocent human life can sometimes be unavoidable. For instance, during the D-Day landings in Normandy, due to uncontrollable circumstances such as bad weather, enemy anti-aircraft fire, and other factors, Allied bombers often overshot their objectives and accidentally bombed civilian centers as well as Allied fighting positions.[3][4] While undoubtedly tragic, few would argue that the invasion would have been inherently unjust unless no civilian lives were lost. In war, a variety of unseen and unavoidable variables can pop-up in an instant and impact battlefield decision making. The advent of modern military technologies helps, but similar problems can still impact the battlespace resulting in tragedy. Communications errors, equipment failures, bad intelligence, and unethical behavior on the part of soldiers sometimes tragically lead to unintended results in conflict. Fatigue and cynicism can also play a role. Decision making on the battlefield changes within split seconds while still being guided by the commander’s intent, which is guided by an overall strategy and “big picture” mission of friendly forces. All of these safeguards can’t prevent the occasional unethical and immoral behavior (human beings aren’t basically good), which is why a clearly defined Rules of Engagement (ROE for shorthand) and Uniform Code of Military Justice are essential for a morally upright military. In the circumstances where soldiers behave unethically or even wickedly towards non-combatants, the military justice system corrects and punishes bad behavior, while promoting and honoring good behavior on the parts of service-members. Leaders should model good behavior and combat bad behavior within the ranks. As retired Marine Corps General James Mattis poignantly puts it, people should know that they have no better friend and no worse enemy “than a United States Marine.” The same is true for the rest of the Armed Services.
As Army Major Pete Hegseth points out, by and large, it has been the United States military (with help from countless invaluable allies worldwide), which has promoted stability, justice, and peace at home and abroad by serving as a sort of world sheriff.[5] Perfect, no, but until a better alternative presents itself, those who love justice shouldn’t feel ashamed for supporting the United States military. As the noted British historian Andrew Roberts argues, when the United States military is weak, wicked men like Adolf Hitler are able to make growing threats to the lives of millions of marginalized people; however, when the American military is strong, even oppressive superpowers like the Soviet Union are forced to tread carefully.[6]
The decision to engage in conflict must be guided by sound moral principles, which includes considering the possible unintended consequences of one’s decision. Good intentions alone are not good enough.
Conclusion
In light of this, pro-lifers are not hypocritical to support either gun ownership or armed conflict provided both are guided by sound moral reasoning. Debates over both are a sign of healthy functioning social conscience.
However, the debate over abortion has nothing to do with what sort of human beings pro-lifers are; it has everything to do with whether the unborn are human, and will be granted recognition as fellow members of the human family. Debates over the Ethics of war, capital punishment, and gun ownership are ultimately irrelevant to the humanity of the unborn and the inhumanity of abortion.
Notes
[1] Hsiao, Tim “Natural Rights, Self-Defense, and the Right to Own Firearms,” The Public Discourse https://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2018/10/42765/
[2] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Guided_bomb
[3] United States Army, “Invasion of Normandy” https://history.army.mil/brochures/normandy/nor-pam.htm
[4] Beevor, Antony D-Day: The Battle for Normandy
[5] Maj. Hegseth, Peter “Who Should Win the Nobel Peace Prize?” PragerUniversity, Nov 11, 2019
[6] Roberts, Andrew “Why America’s Military Must Be Strong” PragerUniversity, May 26, 2014
Recommended resources related to the topic:
Legislating Morality (mp4 download), (DVD Set), (MP3 Set), (PowerPoint download), and (PowerPoint CD) by Frank Turek
Legislating Morality: Is it Wise? Is it Legal? Is it Possible? by Frank Turek (Book)
You Can’t NOT Legislate Morality mp3 by Frank Turek
The Case for Christian Activism (MP3 Set), (DVD Set), and (mp4 Download Set) by Frank Turek
The Apologetics of Abortion mp3 by J. Budziszewski
Reaching Pro-Abortionists for Christ CD by Francis Beckwith
The Case for Christian Activism (MP3 Set), (DVD Set), and (mp4 Download Set) by Frank Turek
Nathan Apodaca is a staff apologist for the Life Training Institute, equipping pro-life advocates to make the case for life. Also a contributing writer at The Millenial Review and CampusReform.
Original Blog Source: http://bit.ly/36ZNbwi
Cosmic Child Abuse? Answering Moral Objections to the Atonement
PodcastPodcast: Play in new window
Subscribe: Apple Podcasts | Spotify | Amazon Music | Android | iHeartRadio | Blubrry | Email | TuneIn | RSS
For two thousand years, Christians have understood the death of Jesus to be substitutionary—a sacrifice that paid for our sins. From the earliest creeds to the teaching of the New Testament to the writings of the Church Fathers to today, this has been a core belief of Christianity throughout its history. But in modern times, this idea is being repudiated as “Cosmic Child Abuse.” On today’s show, we are going to address these questions:
• What is the historic belief of the Christian church on atonement?
• Why does God have wrath and how can that be a good thing?
• Is penal substitutionary atonement a late invention of medieval Christians?
• If God required the sacrifice of his Son, doesn’t that make him a Divine child abuser?
• If I can just forgive people without a sacrifice, why can’t God?
Subscribe on iTunes: http://bit.ly/CrossExamined_Podcast rate and review! Thanks!!!
Subscribe on Google Play: http://bit.ly/CE_Podcast_Google
Subscribe on Spotify: http://bit.ly/CrossExaminedOfficial_Podcast
Subscribe on Stitcher: http://bit.ly/CE_Podcast_Stitcher
10 Ways to Get Your Kids More Interested in Their Faith
Apologetics for ParentsBy Natasha Crain
A couple of weeks ago, I had the opportunity to speak to four groups of parents during the Apologetics Canada conference (incidentally, if you live in the Long Branch, NJ, area, I’ll be speaking at the No Pat Answers conference on April 9). I ended up speaking with a lot of parents after these talks and heard some variant of one particular question repeatedly:
To answer that, I gave several of these parents a snippet of advice from my marketing background.
Every day you probably see or hear some kind of advertisement for buying a new car. If you aren’t currently interested in buying a new car, however, do you notice those ads? Can you even remember the most recent one you saw or heard? Probably not. But let’s say you’re suddenly in the market for a car. Do you pay attention to those ads now? Absolutely. You notice the cars around you on the road, you pay attention to the ads on the radio, and you start keeping an eye out for sales in your mail.
There are some people who just love cars and pay attention to car-related ads all the time. But for most people, car ads become relevant only when they’re in the market for a car. This is called situational relevance.
Similarly, there are some kids who are naturally interested in spiritual matters. But for many, we have to find ways of making faith situationally relevant based on whatever else is going on in their mental life at a given time.
So how do you do that? Here are ten ideas. Note that not all of these will work for all kids. Situational relevance is all about understanding where your kids are mentally right now and working with that. These are simply thought starters.
It’s extremely important to keep in mind that increasing your kids’ interest in God is NOT the same as increasing their interest in church. Those are two separate issues. Theoretically, your kids could be very interested in matters of faith but not like going to church for one reason or another. They won’t necessarily have processed that fact themselves, so you need to ask the questions necessary to differentiate the two. You may well find that your kids would enjoy talking about God with YOU even if they fight the trip to church every week.
Alternatively, your kids could love the experience of church but not be all that interested in God. Beware of having a false sense of confidence that your kids are actively developing their faith just because they like church. Atheists have churches now too. The real question is whether or not your kids are interested in engaging with you on the subject of faith at home.
I strongly believe every family should be setting aside weekly, if not daily, time to engage together in spiritual development (studying the Bible, having conversations about faith, praying, etc.). That said, if your kids are at a certain age and you haven’t already set the precedent of doing this, it can be difficult to implement immediately. To drive their interest, you’ll probably have to work up to it using one of the other tips in this post.
For those with younger kids who are still happy to sit down with their parents at a given time, however, there’s nothing better you can do to develop their interest in faith from the very beginning; you can effectively create a natural interest by making faith an integral part of their lives from a young age. We’ve been doing this several times per week since our twins were 3. They now expect that discussions of faith are part of our everyday lives, and they (now 7) choose to read the Bible and their own devotionals without any prompting. The more they read, the more it leads to questions and conversations of interest to them. When you start early, you can create a snowball of interest.
Parents spend a lot of time either telling their kids about Christianity or having other adults (e.g., at church) tell their kids about Christianity. But how often do we stop and flat-out ask our kids what they believe? How often do we take inventory of how they are actually processing all this information? When you find out what they think about God, Jesus, and the Bible, you’ll quickly see what topics they may be most interested in discussing. For example, you might ask, “Do you believe in God? Why?” If they do, press on to ask, “On a scale of 1 to 100, how sure are you that He exists?” If you find that the number isn’t as high as you would have imagined, it’s a perfect opportunity to have relevant discussions in this area. Or, if they don’t have very good reasons for why they believe (even with strong certainty), you can pique their interest in that area.
One parent, I spoke with at the conference told me how her teenage daughter lost all interest in her faith after something terrible happened to a friend of hers. She was wondering what she could do to get her daughter interested again. I asked if her daughter still believed in God, and she said yes, but that she’s mad at how His world works. The obvious subject of interest for this girl right now (the one most situationally relevant) is the problem of evil and suffering. It wouldn’t make sense to try to get her interested in some random study on the fruits of the Spirit at this particular time. Meet her where she is. Sit and listen to her talk about the questions this event raised for her. Express your own sadness and questions. Tell her you’d like to learn more about it too. Then get a book on the subject to read together or read one on your own and use your knowledge to facilitate relevant conversations.
If your kids have a favorite actor or musician, it’s a situationally relevant opportunity to talk about that celebrity’s views on religion. You can Google the person’s name with the word “religion” to find quotes to discuss. If the celebrity you’re looking for doesn’t happen to have said something interesting about faith, Google “atheist celebrity quotes” or “atheist celebrity memes” and click on the image results. You’ll find many of them from people older kids will know, and it can make for a great discussion. Once you’ve opened some discussion that they find interesting, you can follow up with similar conversations.
Incidentally, here’s a great one from Natalie Portman (discuss what determines the best way to live).
Most kids give the lyrics of songs they listen to no thought. Yet, those lyrics can offer all kinds of opportunities for relevant discussion, given that so many conflicts with a Christian worldview. It shouldn’t be a time to preach at them about how bad the stuff is that they’re listening to (if that is indeed a problem). If you do that, you’ll be closing future doors of conversation with older kids. But it can be a time to objectively look at the lyrics and talk about the worldview presented.
If you really want to get your kids thinking, ask them if they want to take the “atheist challenge.” Tell them you’re going to pretend to be an atheist, and they’ll have to try to convince you that Christianity is true. The novelty of seeing parents take an opposing viewpoint can naturally drive interest in further discussion. Alternatively, the parents can take the “atheist challenge,” and the kids can pretend to not believe in God. You then have to convince your kids Christianity is true. You can bring up all kinds of interesting points they’ve never thought about (see how sneaky/brilliant that is?). (My book has 40 different subjects you could bring up in this context, with all kinds of quotes and examples from atheists!)
Certain personality types love intellectual challenges. My daughter, for example, loves open-ended questions that she can try to answer in the best way possible. If you have a child like that, you can facilitate conversations in a game format by asking, “What would you say if…” Here are a few examples:
What would you say if your friend’s mom said God doesn’t exist? What would you say if someone told you the Bible is 2,000 years old, so it’s not relevant for our lives today? What would you say if someone told you Christians are hypocrites, so they never want to be a Christian? What would you say if someone told you they believe in science, not God? What would you say if someone said they believe in God because their parents do? What would you say if someone said they don’t believe Jesus came back to life because we know that dead people stay dead?
Older teens who are encountering issues of faith and science will appreciate your willingness to watch two different perspectives, particularly if they are struggling with faith doubts. They may not otherwise be willing to talk about faith matters, but would be interested to see your take when you watch an opposing viewpoint. That can then open the door for further discussion that wouldn’t have otherwise happened.
A great science DVD series from a Christian perspective is The Intelligent Design Collection – Darwin’s Dilemma, The Privileged Planet, Unlocking the Mystery of Life.
Kids are very experientially-oriented. While they may be bored to tears if you try to talk them through the differences between Buddhism and Christianity, many would take an interest in learning about Buddhism after actually visiting a Buddhist temple. Take them to see one, and you can bet there will be a lot of questions to talk about. If they develop an interest in learning more about other religions, it’s a perfect opportunity to point the conversations toward understanding how we know Christianity is true.
Recommended resources related to the topic:
Talking with Your Kids about God: 30 Conversations Every Christian Parent Must Have by Natasha Crain (Book)
Keeping Your Kids on God’s Side: 40 Conversations to Help Them Build a Lasting Faith by Natasha Crain (Book)
Courageous Parenting by Jack and Deb Graham (Book)
Proverbs: Making Your Paths Straight Complete 9-part Series by Frank Turek DVD and Download
Forensic Faith for Kids by J. Warner Wallace and Susie Wallace (Book)
God’s Crime Scene for Kids by J. Warner Wallace and Susie Wallace (Book)
Natasha Crain is a blogger, author, and national speaker who is passionate about equipping Christian parents to raise their kids with an understanding of how to make a case for and defend their faith in an increasingly secular world. She is the author of two apologetics books for parents: Talking with Your Kids about God (2017) and Keeping Your Kids on God’s Side (2016). Natasha has an MBA in marketing and statistics from UCLA and a certificate in Christian apologetics from Biola University. A former marketing executive and adjunct professor, she lives in Southern California with her husband and three children.
Original Blog Source: http://bit.ly/2tdB299
Seeking Shalom: A Case for The Way Things Ought to Be
Theology and Christian ApologeticsBy Bob Perry
Sometimes defending God’s existence is easy. You don’t have to try to articulate some fancy philosophical or theological idea. And you don’t have to understand the intricacies of science. All you have to do is be a human being who observes the world in which we live. When you do that, there is no denying that something is drastically wrong. What we see around us is not the way things ought to be. Everybody from the most devoted religious believer to the most ardent atheist knows this. Our common human longing is for a world full of truth, justice, goodness, compassion, and charity. And while there are notable pockets of these things around us, they float in a sea of negativity and corruption.
The fact that everyone realizes this is proof of a powerful idea — that there must be some ideal kind of world we all wish we could experience. A place where things are the way they are supposed to be. And there is an old word the ancients used to describe a place like that. They called it Shalom.
Corrupted Culture
You don’t have to look hard to see a world gone mad. Just watch the news. Years ago, we had a plot by eight-year-olds to kill their teacher. A Google search of that topic today produces several pages of results.
We have researchers who have combined genetic materials to produce human-monkey hybrids — because they can. We have others who seek to push that envelope even further.
And speaking of messing with what it means to be human, how about the growing trend of men “giving birth”? Yes, you read that correctly. Freddy McConnell had a baby in England! Freddy is not really a man, of course. This is not debatable. But we live in a society that condones and patronizes those who demand that we all pretend otherwise, while actual women suffer the consequences.
We see video of people whose organizations generate profits by selling the body parts of aborted babies. But the culture and the courts find more fault with the journalists who expose this practice than with those who engage in it.
A World Gone Bad
Our world is filled with sex trafficking, wars, serial killers, terrorists executing Christians, pornography, oppression, and abuse. Our politicians and news media outlets lie to us. And, maybe most discouragingly, many of our most prominent churches and pastors seem more intent on accommodating the cultural madness than critiquing it.
All of these things make us cringe. Some are uncomfortably bizarre at best, malevolently evil at worst.
But there is a common theme here. Each of these is an example of a way human beings have corrupted the world. We are moral creatures. And we cannot help but recognize, and suffer from, the ramifications of our bad moral choices. The world we see is a reflection of our human nature seeking its own ends.
Crooked Creatures
In the second book of his “Space Trilogy,” Perelandra, C. S. Lewis’s main character, describes his encounter with an eldil — a term Lewis invented to describe something like what we might call an angel. When he first sees the eldil it appears to him as:
Even though he couldn’t explain how, he could tell that the eldil was operating from some otherworldly frame of reference. And when compared to that, the Earth looked strangely crooked.
The Problem of Evil
In his own unique way, C. S. Lewis paints a picture of what we know innately. We recognize that our world is askew, even if we don’t know why. It’s the reason that the “problem of evil” is the most obvious — and most difficult — challenge to the existence of God. Those who doubt God’s existence point to the crooked, corrupted world and ask, “If there is a good God, and He created this world, how can it be such a mess?”
It’s a question that everyone — atheists included — asks. But the answer to that question doesn’t undermine the case for God’s existence at all. It actually does the opposite. We wouldn’t even be asking that question unless we had some intuition about its answer — some notion of a world gone right. But if God does not exist, there is no solution to this “problem” because there is no problem. The world is just the way it is and we suffer in a vacuum of meaningless indifference.
What Do You Mean By “Ought”?
The key is that everyone knows the world is “crooked” — that things are not the way they ought to be. When we say “ought,” we are acknowledging that there is an ideal kind of world in which everyone longs to live. Ought implies a standard of goodness — “a whole system of directions, based outside the Earth.” And that standard is moral perfection. It has to be.
God’s nature is that standard. And a world that reflects that standard is exactly the kind of world we long to inhabit.
If only we could find a place like that!
Shalom
In his book, Not The Way It’s Supposed To Be, Cornelius Plantinga, Jr. offers an insight that I have never forgotten about all this. He defines the Hebrew word shalom. If you’re like me, you may have seen that word translated, “peace.” But Plantinga goes into detail about why that simple definition of the word doesn’t cut it. Shalom is more than just “peace.”
There was a time when we could have described the state of the world as shalom. But it didn’t last long. And when you’re living in a time like ours, shalom appears to be a phantom.
It’s not. It’s an ideal — a description of a place where every human being has always longed to live. And it’s a place that we will all be able to access again.
God Comes Down
God is a down-to-Earth kind of guy. He came down to Earth and took on human form once before. He experienced the pain and suffering of a world that is not the way it ought to be. But in doing so, He offered us a tangible foretaste of shalom.
And he’ll be back.
Shalom.
Don’t be discouraged by the world. There are good ideas that long to be brought to fruition. And there are good people who strive to uphold and defend those ideas both now and in the future. But, more than either of those, there is a good God who is the Author of shalom. Though it sometimes seems elusive, there is a hope-filled time that’s coming for all who choose to seek it. And with that future comes a promise of shalom, unlike anything we can even comprehend.
Recommended resources related to the topic:
If God, Why Evil? (DVD Set), (MP3 Set), and (mp4 Download Set) by Frank Turek
If God Why Evil. Why Natural Disasters (PowerPoint download) by Frank Turek
Why Doesn’t God Intervene More? (DVD Set), (MP3 Set), and (mp4 Download Set) by Frank Turek
Why does God allow Bad Things to Happen to Good People? (DVD) and (mp4 Download) by Frank Turek
Bob Perry is a Christian apologetics writer, teacher, and speaker who blogs about Christianity and the culture at truehorizon.org. He is a Contributing Writer for the Christian Research Journal and has also been published in Touchstone and Salvo. Bob is a professional aviator with 37 years of military and commercial flying experience. He has a B.S., Aerospace Engineering from the U. S. Naval Academy, and an M.A., Christian Apologetics from Biola University. He has been married to his high school sweetheart since 1985. They have five grown sons.
Original Blog Source: http://bit.ly/2Oerwdb
Dios y el tiempo real
EspañolBy William Lane Craig
Introduction
While some of the traditional attributes of God, such as omnipotence or omniscience (particularly divine foreknowledge) have been exhaustively—and one is tempted to say almost exhaustively—analyzed and defended in recent philosophical literature, other divine attributes such as the eternity of God have received scant and generally superficial analysis. [1] Current discussions of the eternity of God have for the most part been conducted in almost complete ignorance of the philosophy of space and time and without any deep knowledge of the theory of relativity and its analysis of time [2] —a notable deficiency, when one thinks about it, for how can one hope to formulate an adequate doctrine of the eternity of God and its relation to time without taking into account what modern philosophy and science have to say about time?
Now Alan Padgett, a PhD candidate under Richard Swinburne, has attempted to remedy that lack by presenting, in full conversation with philosophical and scientific discussions of time, a view of divine eternity that he characterizes as “relative timelessness.” [3] As someone who has recently been working in this very area, I wish to endorse the direction in which Padgett is moving and offer some refinements to this view.
The Eternal Eternity of God: Theory A vs. Theory B of Time
Padgett rejects the classical Plotinian-Augustinian analysis of divine eternity in terms of timeless existence, a view he calls “absolute timelessness.” He regards the classical analysis as inadequate because God, in order to sustain created things, which are always changing in their ontological state, must change in his activity and therefore cannot be timeless.
What Padgett’s article does not make clear, however, is that this line of argument only carries through if one has previously committed oneself to an A-theory of time. [4] According to the A-theorist, temporal becoming is a real, objective feature of the universe; transience is essential to the nature of time, a truth expressed metaphorically by saying that time “flows.” The temporal properties of events cannot be adequately analyzed in terms of prior , simultaneous , and posterior alone, but must include references to the past , present , and future , which are not merely deictic expressions but are irreducibly temporal. The present represents the edge of becoming, and future events merely do not exist yet , but do not exist at all . By contrast, according to the B-theorist, temporal becoming is mind-dependent and purely subjective. Time does not flow, nor do things come into being, except in the sense that at one moment we are aware of them after not having been at an earlier moment. Simultaneous things with different moments on the timeline are equally existent and interrelated to each other by the prior, simultaneous and subsequent relationships to which past, present and future can be reduced. Anything that, from our perspective, existed, exists or will exist in the universe, simply exists (without temporality).
By contrast, on the A-theory of time, the concept of a timeless God who is actually related to the world seems incoherent. Since future states of the universe do not actually exist, God cannot be causing them (even timelessly) to exist; otherwise, they would in fact exist at their respective times. The same holds for past states of the universe. Thus, Aquinas’s argument that God causes timeless things to happen at their respective times only succeeds in showing that things caused by time need not exist eternally, and in fact betrays a B-theoretic view. [5] Even if God immutably wills from eternity that a temporal event exist, there must be attached to that will an exercise of divine causality at the time of the thing’s creation for it to actually happen at that time rather than existing timelessly at that time. The only way to avoid this conclusion would be to deny with Aquinas that God is really related to the world, a totally implausible system of motion that depends on an elaborate Aristotelian metaphysics. [6]
It can be plausibly argued, I think, that the A-theory of time is philosophically and theologically superior to the B-theory. Philosophically, one should agree with D. H. Mellor that “time is such a striking aspect of reality that only the most compelling argument justifies denying it: namely, that the dynamical view of time is contradictory and therefore cannot be true” [7] and then proceed to show that in fact all such attempts to provoke a contradiction, such as McTaggart’s, fail, [8] leaving us secure in our naturally intuitive understanding of the A-theory. No B-theorist, on the other hand, has successfully answered, in my view, the charge that his theory is incoherent because mental dependence on physical becoming requires real becoming in the subjective contents of consciousness. [9] In favor of theory A, one could argue that it offers the most adequate analysis of personal identity [10] and that the temporality of our language and experience is inescapable. [11]
Theologically, there seems to be one decisive reason for Christian theists to reject the B-theory, namely, that it cannot give an adequate analysis of the biblical doctrine of creatio ex nihilo . In the B-theory, creatio ex nihilo is reduced to the ontological dependence of creation on God and the space-time continuum with an edge or boundary. But creation as a whole is co-eternal with God in the sense that it exists as timelessly as He does. There is no state of affairs in the present world that consists in God existing alone without creation. But such an analysis is a wholly inadequate understanding of the biblical doctrine that the created order came into existence and was created by God. Although Aquinas (unlike Bonaventure) thought that one could not philosophically prove this aspect of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo , he was firmly committed to it on the basis of revelation, a fact that contemporary theologians, who sometimes appeal to Aquinas to justify their undue reliance on temporal creativity ex nihilo , tend to forget. [12]
Padgett’s argument against divine timelessness, then, is valid only if the case for an A-theory is successful. What the reader of Padgett’s paper will not realize is that Padgett himself is fully aware of this point and argues for the superiority of the A-theory in his unpublished thesis. On this point, therefore, we are in fundamental agreement.
God’s time and ours
If the A-theory of time is correct, then, and God is in time, the question naturally arises in the context of the theory of relativity: “Whose time is God in?” According to that theory, events that are present to an observer in one inertial frame may be future to an observer in another inertial frame. Certain events will even occur in reverse temporal order relative to some frames compared to others. An observer at rest relative to an observer making a high-speed round trip will experience moments of time or “nows” for which there literally are no correlated simultaneous moments in the traveler’s experience. According to Einstein, neither of these perspectives is privileged, and therefore there is no absolute “now” in the universe. Absolute simultaneity has been banished from the universe in favor of simultaneity relative to a frame of reference. For example, no event occurs “now” in an absolute sense on the planet Neptune or even on the other side of the earth. For observers in relatively mobile reference frames, at this same space-time point they will draw different planes of simultaneity in space-time and thus measure different events, say, on Neptune, as occurring in their respective “nows.” But what is God’s “now”?
Ontological time and measured time
It is to the credit of Padgett’s work that he has cut this Gordian knot by distinguishing between “time” and “measured time.” [13] Time itself, according to Padgett, has to do with God’s eternal duration; measured time is clock time, time according to some metric. Padgett argues that while God is in time, he is not in any measured time, and therefore his “now” is not to be identified with any of the relative “nows” of measured time.
This distinction between ontological time and measured (or empirical) time seems to me to be an extremely important insight, which is a healthy counterweight to the universally repeated and extravagant claims that TRE has forced us to abandon: the classical views of time and space. [14] This erroneous inference rests precisely on the failure to draw the kind of distinction that Padgett has emphasized. That failure can be laid at Einstein’s door. It seems astonishing to me that anyone reading Einstein’s 1905 paper could think that Einstein proved that there is no absolute simultaneity, and that therefore time is relative to reference frames. [15] For the whole theory depends on the acceptance of Einstein’s arbitrary (and, indeed, highly counterintuitive) definition of simultaneity, [16] together with a philosophical positivism of Machian provenance [17] according to which a notion like absolute simultaneity is meaningless if it is empirically undetectable. Since the ether frame of 19th century physics could not be detected empirically, Einstein dismissed it as meaningless, along with his absolute simultaneity, which referred to events occurring simultaneously in the ether frame. By redefining simultaneity in terms of the light signal timing method, Einstein was able to give empirical meaning to the notion of simultaneity, but the simultaneity that emerges from the theory is relative due to the invariant speed of light. Since light signals are measured as having the speed c regardless of the motion of the sender or receiver of the signals, two relatively moving observers will measure the same event occurring at different times, which goes against the traditional notion of simultaneity. [18]
Anyone who is not a positivist, and therefore rejects Einstein’s definitions, would regard these relatively soulful observers as deluded because of the nature of their measurements, which cannot detect real time. [19] In a real sense, he would not regard Einstein’s theory as a theory about time and space at all, but, as Frank put it, as “a system of hypotheses about the behavior of light rays, rigid bodies, and mechanisms, from which new results about this behavior can be derived.” [20] Trapped in our locally moving frames, we may be forced to measure time by devices that are inadequate to detect real time, but that by no means implies that there is no such time. The fact that uniformly moving clocks run slowly says more about our clocks than about the nature of time. Thus, Einstein’s theory can be regarded as pragmatically useful and scientifically fruitful without having to regard absolute simultaneity and absolute time as abolished.
One might think that Einstein’s positivism was simply a historically accidental feature of the theory, but it is not part of the philosophical foundations of that theory. Such an attitude, however, would be mistaken. As J.S. Bell points out, it is primarily this philosophical positivism that serves to distinguish the Einsteinian interpretation of lavTRE from the Lorentzian interpretation, which differentiates between ontological time and measured time:
Since the Lorentzian interpretation of the TER is empirically equivalent to Einstein’s interpretation, the only way the latter can rule out the former is by a positivist critique of notions of absolute simultaneity, and so on. According to Lawrence Sklar,
Now this constitutes a truly serious drawback of Einstein’s interpretation. As Healey observes, although positivists tried to restrict the content of scientific theories in order to ensure that they were meaningful, “more recently positivism has come under such sustained attack that opposition has become almost orthodoxy in the philosophy of science.” [24] Philosophers of religion need not be reminded of the untenability of positivism in view of their radical critique of religious language, which would regard Padgett’s distinction between God’s time and our time as cognitively meaningless.
Since God is in time, therefore, it is evident that His is not the time that is determined by Einstein’s operational definitions; subject to dilation, the relativity of simultaneity, and the reversal of events. Rather, God’s time is true A-series time, determined by the succession of events in divine consciousness and activity and characterized by the absolute “now” of the present and the edge of becoming. His is, to borrow D.H. Mellor’s phrase, “Real Temporality.”
So I think it’s rather unfortunate that Padgett chose to call his view “relative timelessness,” because it is precisely the opposite. It is God who exists in true ontological time, while finite observers, restricted to our locally moving reference frames dependent on the light signal timing of clocks, have to make do with our manufactured measured time. Contrary to Padgett, ordinary use of time concepts cannot justify calling God relatively timeless, since our intuitive view of time is an A-theoretic view, and this is precisely the time in which God lives. Thus, the view Padgett presents is better labeled “Real Temporality.”
God’s time and cosmic time
But how does God’s time relate to our own? Padgett answers that while we are in God’s time, God is not in any measured time. But this answer seems to me to be factually false. From the perspective of God in the real time of the A-series, there is an absolute present in which he is now aware of what is happening in the universe, and he is now causally causing the events in the universe. But if, as we saw in our critique of divine timelessness, God’s causally sustaining the universe in being is simultaneous with the events being sustained, then there must be an absolute cosmic “now” that describes the state of the universe as it is present to God. Future events for this moment do not exist at all, since God has not yet caused them. But is there a frame of reference in the universe that produces a measured time that can be naturally associated with the succession of such moments? Yes, there is. It is not, in fact, the inertial frame of any spatially local observer, but the reference frame of the cosmic expansion of space itself. The relativity of simultaneity depends on the assumption that there is no preferred reference frame; but if there is a preferred frame, as the Lorentzian interpretation would have it, then the relations of simultaneity in it would be absolute, and relativity would apply to all other frames. But the frame associated with cosmic expansion seems naturally suited to such a privileged position. Michael Shallis explains:
We must not forget that Einstein proposed his Special Theory long before cosmic expansion was discovered, so that in the absence of the characterless and dying ether, there seemed to be no empirical basis for positing any universal frame beyond the multitude of locally moving frames. But with the discovery that the universe is expanding, it became possible to imagine a universal frame of reference by imagining observers associated with fundamental particles (i.e., galaxies or galaxy clusters) having mutual recessional velocities. In fact, the “gas” constituted by these fundamental particles is at rest relative to the expansion of cosmic space and is therefore an ether. As early as 1920, Eddington acknowledged that the General Theory of Relativity postulated a kind of cosmic time, but he objected that such cosmic time was unknowable and therefore irrelevant to observers in moving local frames. [26] Within a few years, however, the expansion of the universe predicted by Einstein’s field equations (minus the cosmological constant) had been confirmed by observational astronomy, thus providing a sort of cosmic clock that the abandonment of the aether theory seemed to have served no practical purpose. Of course, it might still be objected that this universal time is unknowable and therefore irrelevant. But not only does this objection seem to be infected with a defunct verificationist attitude, it does not even seem to be true. Recent observations have revealed an apparent anisotropy in the cosmic microwave background radiation that is due to the motion of the earth relative to the cosmic reference frame, resulting in what has been characterized as a “new aether wind” of about 360 kilometers per second. [27] Comments by P.C. W. Davies,
Not only, then, is there cosmic time, but we even have a pretty good idea of what time it is.
Given the existence of this cosmic time, I believe that the moments of God’s actual time, the A-series—while perhaps not identical to the moments of measured cosmic time—do coincide. God’s ontological time clearly exceeds the cosmic time by which the former could have preceded the latter (imagine God leading creation by counting “1, 2, 3, … fiat lux !”), but once cosmic time comes into existence, its moments would coincide with the moments of actual time. How could they fail to do so? If the duration of the universe is measured in cosmic time at 15 billion years from the singularity, isn’t the duration of God’s creative activity in actual time the same duration? In God’s “now” the universe has (present time) certain specific and unique properties, for example, a certain radius, a certain density, a certain background temperature, etc., but in the cosmic “now” it has all the identical properties, and so it is with each successive “now.” Is it not obvious that these “nows” coincide and designate the same present?
Perhaps we can state this consideration more formally by the following principle:
Since in real time there is a temporal interval or duration during which a certain physical description of the universe is true, and since in cosmic time there is a similar interval, it follows from P that those intervals of real and cosmic time coincide. Note that the argument makes no reference to any particular metrication of time and therefore does not depend on it. It seems to me, then, that real time and cosmic time should naturally be regarded as coinciding since the beginning of cosmic time.
Padgett’s objections to this understanding of the relationship of God’s time to measured time appear to be rather weak. He first objects that God is not subject to the laws of nature, as anything in measured time must be. He argues that since God acts freely rather than uniformly and has the power to alter the laws of nature, he cannot be in measured time. But why could not God’s time contain its own intrinsic metric, as Newton believed, that physical clocks provide a more or less “sensible” measure? [29] In this case, an ideal physical clock would measure God’s time. Furthermore, the premise that anything in measured time must be subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur. It is the measuring instrument , i.e. the clock , that must be subject to the laws of nature, not the object of measurement, which could be a totally random process. To say that 15 billion years ago God created the universe is not to say that God is subject to the laws of planetary motion, but simply to apply to God’s time a conventional metric that marks a duration equal to the duration of the earth’s orbit around the sun. That is to say that the duration during which God thought or did something is equal to, say, the duration it would take the earth to complete a certain number of orbits. Even on a purely mundane level, global proper time near the singularity is not a direct count of simple, real phenomena, since the earth will not have actually completed, say, 1010 orbits in the last 1010 years and even a cesium atomic clock would not have ticked at very early intervals. Rather, global proper time is an elaborate mathematical extrapolation of physical phenomena. [30] Similarly, any arbitrarily chosen metric can be applied to the duration of God or the universe.
Padgett anticipates such an objection, supposing that the universe might be thought of as acting as a kind of clock to measure the length of God’s time. But let’s be quite clear about this, for the universe does not merely act as a clock for God. The universe is a clock; it is God’s clock. For example, some conventional unit of God’s time might be the time it takes for the radius of the universe to increase by a certain factor. Padgett retorts that it does not follow that because two events e1 and e2 are one hour apart in one frame of reference, they are one hour apart in God’s time. He appeals to time dilation between relatively moving frames to show that the duration between two identical events can be measured diversely. But the analogy fails here, for we are not comparing two relatively moving frames using light signals to synchronize their respective clocks. Since God is actually related to the universe and not moving relative to it, there is no basis for any relativity of simultaneity between His present and the cosmic present. God is a disembodied Mind that uses a physical clock.
Padgett objects that cosmic time is contingent and applies only to our universe. We cannot, therefore, suppose that it applies to anything beyond it. But we have no reason, biblical or philosophical, to think that there are other universes. Parsimony justifies the assumption that ours is the only universe. In that case, it only follows that actual time and cosmic time contingently coincide ; there are possible worlds in which they do not. [31] But why is that an objection? Since God’s decision to create was free, cosmic time is essentially contingent; indeed, I should say that even actual time is contingent. [32] But since cosmic time exists, there is no objection to holding that God’s time contingently coincides with it for the duration of the cosmos.
Padgett’s second objection to this view is that measured time is relative to a particular frame of reference, which need not apply to God. He argues that because God transcends space, his life need not occur in our four-dimensional space-time continuum. Therefore, his life is not limited to the temporal dimension of our space-time.
This objection raises some interesting questions about divine omnipresence, [33] which we can give up. One might also question whether the objection has sufficient insight into the difference between parameter time and coordinate time. [34] In Newtonian mechanics, time functions as a parameter, which is entirely independent of space. However, in the theory of relativity, time functions not only as a parameter, but also as a coordinate that is joined with spatial coordinates. However, that theory is susceptible to reformulation entirely in terms of parameter time. One might therefore argue that God is in measured time, but that means therefore parameter time, not coordinate time, so that God’s independence from space is preserved. However, the essential point to be made is that God’s time can be measured by coordinate time without His being also measured by spatial coordinates, because on the understanding I have proposed, moments of ontological time can be thought of as coinciding with moments of measured time without being identical to them. Thus, even if it is true that a being whose duration is measured exclusively by coordinate time must also have spatial coordinates, it does not follow that a being whose duration in ontological time coincides with its duration in measured time must also be in space. Again, the fact that this coincidence is contingent constitutes no objection, but it is in fact implied by traditional theism.
It seems to me, therefore, that Padgett’s view needs to be refined with respect to the relationship between ontological time and measured time, and hence between God’s time and our own. Real time is the time of the A-series in which God thinks and acts and in which things come into being; the moments of this time coincide from the beginning of the universe with the moments of cosmic time determined by ideal stationary clocks with respect to the expansion of space itself.
Conclusion
I believe, therefore, that Padgett has gone a long way toward formulating a philosophically sound and scientifically informed doctrine of divine eternity that is also faithful to biblical revelation. The philosophical and theological grounds for preferring an A-theory of time also provide justification for rejecting the Plotine-Augustinian doctrine of divine timelessness because that theory seems incompatible with the real relationship of a timeless God to the world. God thinks and acts in real time—that is, the A-series of temporal moments, in which becoming, absolute simultaneity, and absolute “now” exist—and his relationship to time must be characterized as “true temporality.” In contrast, by conventionally defining simultaneity in terms of the light-signal method of clock synchronization and by adopting arbitrary metrics to quantify time, men have developed a measured time, which is extremely malleable to relatively moving timekeepers. Since God is not in any inertial frame, his time, ontological time, is not subject to these effects. However, in our universe, due to its isotropic expansion from an initial singularity, there is cosmic time that records successive moments in the history of the universe. Although ontological time may precede (or succeed) measured cosmic time—whether ontological time has a beginning is an issue we have not sought to judge in this article—nevertheless, the moments of ontological time and cosmic time will coincide for the duration of cosmic time, since they refer to the identical succession of states in the universe. To object that this makes God subject to the laws of nature is a non sequitur , since it is our clocks that must be subject. To object that this view traps God in spacetime is equally mistaken, since ontological time only contingently coincides with cosmic time, so that God in ontological time can exist at a time that coincides with a measured moment of time without having to possess coordinate space as well. One of the interesting implications of this understanding is that a Lorentzian rather than an Einsteinian interpretation of the special theory of relativity is correct: there is a preferred reference frame in which light propagates with speed c , and relativistic effects are due to local motion relative to this frame. With these refinements, Padgett’s view of divine eternity appears to be coherent and plausible.
Grades
[1] Note that the literature on divine eternity is so sparse that it did not even merit a mention in Philosophy of Religion: an Annotated Bibliography of Twentieth Century Writings in English (New York: Garland Publishing, 1978).
[2] See, for example. Nelson Pike, God and Timelessness (New York: Schocken Books, 1970); Stephen T. Davis, Logic and the Nature of God (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1983); Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “Eternity,” Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981):429-58.
[3] Alan Padgett, “God and Time: Toward a New Doctrine of Divine Timeless Eternity,” Religious Studies 25 (1989): 209-15); see further idem , “Divine Eternity and the Nature of Time” (Ph.D. thesis, Oxford University, 1988) [now published as God, Eternity, and the Nature of Time (New York: St. Martin’s, 1992)].
[4] The distinction between the A and B series of temporal events was originally made by J. M. E. McTaggart, The Nature of Existence , 2 vols., ed. C. D. Broad (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927; rep. ed.: 1968), Book V, chs. 33; for discussion, see C. D. Broad, Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy , 2 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1938; rep. ed.: New York: Octagon Books, 1976), 2:265–344. See also Richard Gale, “Introduction” to Section II: “The Static versus the Dynamic Temporal,” in The Philosophy of Time , ed. R. Gale (London: Macmillan, 1968), pp. 65–85.
[5] On the connection between classical conceptions of divine eternity and a B theory of time, see Wm. L. Craig, The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez , Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 7 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1988), pp. 116–21; idem, “St. Anselm on Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingency,” Laval théologique et philosophique 42 (1986):93–104. See also Delmas Lewis, “Eternity, Time and Tenselessness,” Faith and Philosophy 5 (1988):72–86.
[6] For a brief critique, see Wm. L. Craig, “God, Time, and Eternity,” Religious Studies 14 (1979):497-503.
[7] D.H. Mellor, Real Time (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 5.
[8] See refutation in Paul Horwich, Asymmetries in Time (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 26–27. Horwich’s own rejection of A-theory is based on the mistaken view that an A-theory entails the denial of semantic bivalence for contingent future propositions.
[9] Such an objection needs to be formulated more carefully, but is detailed in Milic Capek, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics (Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1961), p. 165; idem, “Introduction,” in The Concepts of Space and Time , ed. M. Capek, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), p. XLVII; Frederick Ferré, “Grünbaum on Temporal Becoming: A Critique,” International Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1972):432-33; James A. McGilvray, “A Defense of Physical Becoming,” Erkenntnis 14 (1979):275-99.
[10] See Ronald C. Hoy, “Becoming and Persons,” Philosophical Studies 34 (1978):269-80.
[11] See Quentin Smith, “Problems with the New Tenseless Theory of Time,” Philosophical Studies 52 (1987):371-92 and the literature cited therein.
[12] See, for example, John Polkinghorne, “Cosmology and Creation,” paper presented at the conference “The Origin of the Universe,” Colorado State University, Ft. Collins, Colorado, September 22-25, 1988. The proceedings will probably be published by SUNY Press.
[13] This much-misunderstood distinction was carefully worked out by Newton himself in the Scholium to the Definitions at the beginning of his Principia (Isaac Newton, Sir Isaac Newton’s ‘Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy’ and his ‘System of the World’, trans. Andrew Motte, rev. with appendix by Florian Cajori, 2 vols. [Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1966], pp. 6–12). Cf. M. F. Cleugh, Time and its Importance in Modern Thought (London: Methuen, 1937), pp. 29–67; Philipp Frank, Philosophy of Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1957), pp. 140–43; Herbert Dingle, “Time in Philosophy and Physics,” Philosophy 54 (1979):99–104.
[14] Typical are Hawking’s recent statements: “…the theory of relativity puts an end to the idea of absolute time […] The theory of relativity forces us to fundamentally change our ideas of space and time.” (Stephen Hawking, A Brief History of Time [New York: Bantam Books, 1988], pp. 21, 23).
[15] A. Einstein, “On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies,” in The Principle of Relativity , trans. W. Perrett and GB Jeffery with notes by A. Sommerfield (New York: Dover Publications, 1952), pp. 37-65.
[16] Two spatially separated events are simultaneous if they both occur at the same clock hours as recorded by two synchronized clocks A and B situated respectively at the locations of the events, where A and B are stationary relative to each other and B reads the same as A at the temporal midpoint of the time required for A to send a light signal to B and receive it back. The assumption is that A and B are not moving with reference to the ether-frame, so the travel time of the signal is no longer (or shorter) on the return leg of its journey. Now, clearly, unless one is an operationalist, this is not what is meant by simultaneity, and unless one is a positivist, the underlying assumption of the definition is entirely gratuitous.
[17] The influence of Mach’s positivism on Einstein and his Special Theory of Relativity is widely acknowledged by historians of science, but surprisingly rarely discussed by philosophers exploring the philosophical foundations of that theory. For discussion, see G. Holton, “Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality,” in Ernst Mach: Physicist and Philosopher , Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1970), pp. 167-77; P. Frank, “Einstein, Mach, and Logical Positivism,” in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P. A. Schilpp, Library of Living Philosophers 7 (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1949), pp. 271-86; H. Reichenbach, “The Philosophical Significance of the Theory of Relativity”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 289-311.
[18] For alternative operational definitions of “simultaneity” and “synchronization” that preserve absolute simultaneity, see T. Sjödin, “On the One-Way Velocity of Light and its Possible Measurability”, paper presented at the conference Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory , British Society for the Philosophy of Science, Imperial College, London, September 16–19, 1988.
[19] This is, in fact, the modern Lorentzian interpretation of SRT, which holds that velocity affects our measuring devices, so that moving rods and clocks contract slowly. Such an interpretation does not commit us to a substantive ether, but merely to an ether- frame , i.e. a privileged frame of reference. The fact that the Lorentzian interprets longitudinal contraction and time dilation as not merely apparent but real cannot be cited as a disadvantage of the theory, since the Einsteinian must also postulate real contraction and dilation (see Peter Kroes’ paper “The Physical Status of Time Dilation within the Special Theory of Relativity,” at the conference mentioned in note 18; see also Dennis Dieks, “The `Reality’ of the Lorentz Contraction,” Zeitschrift fur allgemeine Wissenschafts-theorie 15/2). The difference between the two on this point is that the Lorentzian offers some explanation for these effects, while the Einsteinian does not. The decision between a Lorentzian and an Einsteinian interpretation of SRT will probably depend on whether God’s time can plausibly be interpreted to coincide with some coordinate time, which would therefore be the privileged time of the aether frame.
[20] Frank, Philosophy of Science , p. 140.
[21] J. S. Bell, “How to Teach Special Relativity,” in Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics , ed. JS Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 77.
[22] Lawrence Sklar, “Time, reality and relativity,” in Reduction, Time and Reality , ed. R. Healey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 141.
[23] Ibid., p. 132
[24] R. Healey, “Introduction,” in Reduction, Time and Reality , p. vii.
[25] Muchael Shallis, “Time and Cosmology,” in The Nature of Time , ed. Raymond Flood and Michael Lockwood (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp. 68-69.
[26] Arthur Eddington, Space, Time and Gravitation , Cambridge Science Classics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 168:
[27] GF Smoot, MV Gorenstein, and RA Muller, “Detection of Anisotropy in the Cosmic Blackbody Radiation,” Physical Review Letters 39 (1977): 899.
[28] PCW Davies, “Space-Time Singularities in Cosmology and Black Hole Evaporations,” in The Study of Time III , ed. JT Fraser, N. Lawrence, and D. Park (Berlin: Springer Verlag, 1978), p. 76. I have corrected spelling errors in the quote.
[29] See Charles W. Misner, Kip S. Thorne, John A. Wheeler, Gravitation (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1973), pp. 813-14. The authors’ attempt to criticize proper global time as inadequately physical fails to appreciate the counterfactual nature of the application of the metric; elapsed time is measured as if an atomic clock were present and running.
[30] For a helpful discussion see Peter Kroes, Time: Its Structure and Its Role in Physical Theories , Synthese Library 179 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), p. 49.
[31] By postulating a cosmic rotation of matter, Gödel was able to work out model universes satisfying Einstein’s field equations in which there is no cosmic time (Kurt Gödel, “A Remark about the Relationship between Relativity Theory and Idealistic Philosophy”, in Albert Einstein , pp. 557–62). In such worlds, Padgett’s view would be correct. But in fact, there is cosmic time, and it naturally appears to coincide with real time.
[32] See my “God, Time and Eternity,” pp. 497-503, where I argue that God existing without creation is timeless and that He enters time at its beginning with His creation of the universe. Since creation is a freely willed act of God, the existence of actual time is therefore contingent.
[33] See, for example, Eddington’s observation:
[34] See Kroes, Time , pp. 60-96.
William Lane Craig is an American Baptist Christian analytic philosopher and theologian. Craig’s philosophical work focuses on the philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and philosophy of time. His theological interests lie in historical Jesus studies and philosophical theology.
Original Blog: http://bit.ly/3aWccf2
Translated by Jairo Izquierdo
I Lost Motivation for my God-given Passion… Now What?
Theology and Christian ApologeticsBy Jeremy Linn
You were driven. Each day you were excited to take another step forward. God seemed to be doing amazing things.
Now, months later, your passion has disappeared. Each day you feel worn out and progressively waste more of your time. You wonder if God will ever use you to the same extent as you once experienced.
What happened? Have you lost motivation to pursue the primary passion God has given you?
I certainly have felt this way before. Upon the start of a new ministry, I was constantly motivated to keep taking steps and saw God do incredible things in the process.
Then over time, the amazing moments started to fade. Team communication halted. And my motivation plummeted to the point I didn’t know what to do next.
This path led me to wonder – what problems could have led me to lose motivation for something I had such a strong passion for?
To begin working through this question, I wrote down nine problems that could cause you to lose motivation for your God-given passion and listed action steps that could help to address each one. And now, I share the results with you. As you skim through the list, feel free to skip over the problems that don’t affect you, and focus more on the ones that may be causing you to lose motivation.
PROBLEM #1 – A lack of communication causes delays and stagnation.
You want to take action but can’t seem to because you need input from others first. With communication shut down, your motivation stalls out.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #2 – You are comparing yourself with people going down a similar path who appear to be more “successful.”
You think you will never be as successful as the person or group you have in mind, so wonder what the point is of continuing. The doubts in your mind cause a loss of motivation.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #3: A fear of failure is holding you back.
You fear your actions won’t lead to results that match or exceed your expectations, causing you to wonder if it’s worth stating to take those actions.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #4: Your time is taken up by average things that don’t provoke inspiration and excitement.
You’re not spending your time on “great” things that spark your passion. Over time, your motivation dulls as you lack moments of excitement for what lies ahead.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #5: A sin issue provokes shame and doubts that you are “worthy” to act on your God-given passion.
You don’t push forward with your passion because you already don’t feel “good enough” or “spiritual enough” for it.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #6: You feel disconnected from God compared to how you used to feel.
This sense of disconnection could be caused by a variety of factors beyond sin issues – an overwhelming sense of busyness and isolation from other Christians are examples.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #7: You lack a connection with people you can share your passion with.
You feel alone in the pursuit of your passion and don’t receive encouragement to continue forward, which drives you into self-doubt and a gradual loss of motivation. Action Steps:
PROBLEM #8: You don’t have a clear vision or goals related to your passion.
While you have an idea of what your passion is, you have little sense of direction for what to do with it, and thus don’t have a foundation built which will drive motivation.
Action Steps:
PROBLEM #9: You feel overloaded by the commitment required for things you’re involved with.
The resulting stress causes your physical and mental health to suffer, along with your relationship with God. You lose motivation to take action on just about anything, including your passion area.
Action Steps:
This list is not exhaustive, nor is it meant to give you the perfect solution to get you on the motivation track again. But the action points can at least get you out of inactivity, and back into a gradual buildup of motivation.
The main idea is this: when you feel like you’ve lost motivation, ask yourself what problems could lead to that loss. Once you identify potential problems, plan to take one or two small action steps that could help alleviate the problem.
And through the process, pray for wisdom and set your focus on God.
Recommended resources related to the topic:
The Great Apologetics Adventure by Lee Strobel (Mp3)
Living Loud: Defending Your Faith by Norman Geisler (Book)
Practical Apologetics in Worldview Training by Hank Hanegraaff (Mp3)
Jeremy is the co-founder of the ministry Twin Cities Apologetics and is an accountant for a law firm in Minneapolis, Minnesota. He’s also going to Bethel Seminary for a graduate degree in a program called Christian Thought (basically Apologetics!). Outside of Apologetics, Jeremy enjoys sports, playing guitar, and making videos.
Life is Like Football
PodcastPodcast: Play in new window
Subscribe: Apple Podcasts | Spotify | Amazon Music | Android | iHeartRadio | Blubrry | Email | TuneIn | RSS
Green Bay Packers quarterback Aaron Rodgers has left Christianity because he believes it is too exclusive, too binary, and that the Christian God wants to condemn most people to a fiery Hell. Join Frank on Super Bowl weekend as he responds to Aaron’s characterization of Christianity and goes on to point out that all of reality (including football) is binary and that truth is exclusive. In fact, Frank points out that life is a lot like football in at least seven ways.
Subscribe on iTunes: http://bit.ly/CrossExamined_Podcast rate and review! Thanks!!!
Subscribe on Google Play: http://bit.ly/CE_Podcast_Google
Subscribe on Spotify: http://bit.ly/CrossExaminedOfficial_Podcast
Subscribe on Stitcher: http://bit.ly/CE_Podcast_Stitcher
William Lane Craig Lectures on The Evidence for The Resurrection of Jesus
Jesus Christ, Theology and Christian ApologeticsBy Wintery Knight
Here is Dr. William Lane Craig giving a long-form argument for the historical event of the resurrection of Jesus and taking questions from the audience.
The speaker’s introduction goes for 6 minutes, then Dr. Craig speaks for 35 minutes, then it’s a period of questions and answers with the audience. The total length is 93 minutes, so quite a long period of Q&A. The questions in the Q&A period are quite good.
Introduction:
Fact #1: the burial of Jesus following his crucifixion
Fact #2: on the Sunday following his crucifixion, Jesus’ tomb was found empty by some women
Fact #3: Jesus appeared to various people in various circumstances after his death
Fact #4: the earliest Christians proclaimed their belief in the resurrection of Jesus
Dr. Craig then asks which hypothesis explains all four of these facts. He surveys a number of naturalistic hypotheses, such as the hallucination theory or various conspiracy theories. All of these theories deny one or more of the minimal facts that have been established and accepted by the broad spectrum of historians. In order to reject the resurrection hypothesis, a skeptic would have to deny one of the four facts or propose an explanation that explains those facts better than the resurrection hypothesis.
I listened to the Q&A period while doing housekeeping, and I heard lots of good questions. Dr. Craig gives very long answers to the questions. One person asked why we should trust the claim that the Jewish leaders really did say that the disciples stole the body. Another one asked why we should take the resurrection as proof that Jesus was divine. Another asks about the earthquake in Matthew and whether it is intended to be historical or apocalyptic imagery. Dr. Craig is also asked about the Jewish scholar Geza Vermes, and how many of the minimal facts he accepts. Another questioner asked about the ascension.
If you are looking for a good book to read on this topic, the best introductory book on the resurrection is “The Case for the Resurrection of Jesus,” and the best comprehensive book is “The Resurrection of Jesus.”
Recommended resources related to the topic:
Early Evidence for the Resurrection by Dr. Gary Habermas (DVD), (Mp3) and (Mp4)
Cold Case Resurrection Set by J. Warner Wallace (books)
Did Jesus Rise from the Dead? By Dr. Gary Habermas (book)
Jesus, You and the Essentials of Christianity – Episode 14 Video DOWNLOAD by Frank Turek (DVD)
Original Blog Source: http://bit.ly/36kqnqz
How Understanding Divine Omniscience Helps Anxiety
Theology and Christian ApologeticsBy Brian Chilton
While apologetics is a major focus in my life, it is only eclipsed by a love for theology. I am a big picture kind of guy. That’s why systematic theology has always intrigued me. Systematic theology examines the major themes of Scripture and organizes those themes into patterns and structures. One could say that I went a little crazy with my theological studies. While I have over 18 graduate hours in apologetics, biblical studies, and church history; I will have over 30 hours in graduate-level studies of theology by the time I finish my Ph.D. So, yeah. You could say that I like theology a little bit.
Another aspect of my life that is important to note for the sake of this article is that I also suffer from bouts of anxiety. My anxiety is not major. However, it is something that I have combated for years. Agoraphobia is one such area. I love people. I love being in the ministry. However, long bouts of extended social gatherings wear me down especially if those gatherings are loud and boisterous.
You may be left asking, “Why is this guy talking about theology and anxiety?” Theology has a major calming effect when a person understands certain aspects of God’s nature. One such calming attribute is God’s omniscience. Omniscience is a compound word consisting of two Latin words; Omnis meaning “all” or “of all things,” and Scientia meaning “knowledge.” Thus, omniscience indicates one’s ability to know all things. God is the only Being who could possess this level of knowledge. Millard Erickson links God’s omniscience with God’s infinite nature. By infinite, this means that “not only is God unlimited but that he is illimitable. In this respect, God is unlike anything we experience” (Erickson, Christian Theology, 243). When God’s knowledge is linked with his infinite nature, one will note that God’s “understanding is immeasurable” (Erickson, Christian Theology, 243).
God’s omniscience means that God knows all there is to know and everything that can be known. So, how does understanding God’s divine omniscient nature help with anxiety? I contend that it helps in three areas.
Jesus emphasized the peace that comes from understanding God’s omniscience, noting that if God could clothe the flowers of the field and feed the birds of the air, then God would most certainly care for his own in greater fashion (Matt. 6:25–34). If God knows all there is to know, if God knows all that everyone does, if he knows our future, and cares for us; then, what do we have to fear? For, if God is for us, then who can be against us (Rom. 8:31)? Human anxiety melts before the brilliant assurance of God’s omniscient nature.
Resources
Erickson, Millard J. Christian Theology. Third Edition. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2013.
Recommended resources related to the topic:
What is God Really Like? A View from the Parables by Dr. Frank Turek (DVD, Mp3, and Mp4)
What is God Like? Look to the Heavens by Dr. Frank Turek (DVD and Mp4)
Why Is God Ignoring Me? (DVD), and (mp4 Download) by Gary Habermas
How to Interpret Your Bible by Dr. Frank Turek DVD Complete Series, INSTRUCTOR Study Guide, and STUDENT Study Guide
How NOT to Interpret the Bible: A Lesson from the Cults by Thomas Howe mp3
Can We Understand the Bible? by Thomas Howe Mp3 and CD
Brian G. Chilton is the founder of BellatorChristi.com, the host of The Bellator Christi Podcast, and the author of the Layman’s Manual on Christian Apologetics. He received his Master of Divinity in Theology from Liberty University (with high distinction); his Bachelor of Science in Religious Studies and Philosophy from Gardner-Webb University (with honors); and received certification in Christian Apologetics from Biola University. Brian is enrolled in the Ph.D. program in Theology and Apologetics at Liberty University and is a member of the Evangelical Theological Society and the Evangelical Philosophical Society. Brian has been in the ministry for nearly 20 years and serves as the Senior Pastor of Westfield Baptist Church in northwestern North Carolina.
Original Blog Source: http://bit.ly/2Rolhpc
Un argumento psicológico contra la teoría de las alucinaciones de Gerd Lüdemann sobre la Resurrección de Jesús
EspañolPor Kike Medina
Introducción:
Como es común entre ciertos círculos ateos (sobre todo en redes sociales) podemos encontrar muchas objeciones hacia la existencia de Jesús, sus milagros y su resurrección; Algunas objeciones son decentes y otras son verdaderamente pésicas, formuladas con mucho desconocimiento filosófico y argumentativo, acompañado de ciertas actitudes y prejuicios negativos hacia los cristianos y su fe.
Pero hay una objeción que ha ganado fuerza durante los últimos años y ha sido objeto de debate entre muchos apologistas de alto prestigio, sobre todo porque forma parte de una especie de “grupo” de objeciones hacia la resurrección de Jesús y es aquella que postula que los apóstoles y discípulos de Jesús alucinaron al verlo luego de haber muerto por crucifixión y resucitado tres días después.
La teoría de las alucinaciones propuesta por el historiador Gerd Lüdemann, parece ser consistente y probablemente una objeción que puede tambalear los cimientos de la fe de muchas personas, sobre todo a aquellas que no están muy bien instruidas en la defensa de la fe. Muchos la han abordado desde distintas perspectivas y han creado objeciones, sobre todo desde una perspectiva histórica-metodológica. Sin embargo, hasta donde sé, no se ha desarrollado una objeción que va más acorde a la naturaleza de la teoría de Lüdemann.
El objetivo principal de este escrito es abordar la teoría desde un punto de vista psicológico, para ver si realmente es consistente con lo que objeta y así poder dar una herramienta más para todos aquellos que recién abordan esta teoría y recién inician en la defensa de la fe.
La teoría de las alucinaciones
Antes de empezar a abordar de lleno con la objeción de Lüdemann, hay que hacer dos importantes aclaraciones: Sigo el mismo pensamiento del Dr.Craig cuando él dice que “está de acuerdo con Lüdemann en que la resurrección de Jesús es el punto central de la religión cristiana”, y que “la tarea del historiador es muy parecida a la del abogado litigante; examinar a los testigos para reconstruir el curso más probable de los acontecimientos”.[1] En efecto, quizá no podemos saber si un hecho histórico pasó con una certeza del cien por ciento, pero podemos hacer historia recopilando datos, formulando hipótesis y ver cuál de todas nuestras explicaciones es la más razonable.
Ahora bien, parece que Lüdemann encuentra cierta satisfacción psicológica en su propia teoría, pues al negar a Cristo es común que una persona sienta cierta culpa por haber abandonado un estilo de vida, como le puede suceder a un empleado que es despedido de una mega empresa de alto nivel. Sin embargo, esto es irrelevante, dado que, si Lüdemann realizó tal explicación de la resurrección de Jesús y la experiencia de los discípulos debido a esa culpa, no valoraremos su veracidad partiendo desde este punto, pues eso sería solo un ataque personal, además de que su estado emocional y mental también carece de importancia para este análisis.
La teoría de las alucinaciones es desarrollada partiendo desde el punto de vista anímico y mental de los discípulos. Por ejemplo, la explicación de la alucinación de Pedro, es presentada de la siguiente manera:
Supongamos que es totalmente válido; sería lógico creer que Pedro pudo haber alucinado a Jesús debido a su culpa, pues lo había negado tres veces. Luego de esto, tal alucinación fue contagiada hacia otras personas que no compartían el trauma de Pedro.
Luego de que se creara la leyenda de la tumba vacía y que Jesús se había aparecido a las mujeres en la misma tumba, Pablo luchaba internamente con la culpa mientras trabajaba bajo el yugo de la ley y su celo al perseguir cristianos era una manifestación de una atracción secreta por el mensaje cristiano. Lüdemann ofrece esta explicación sobre la “alucinación” de Pablo:
De hecho, desconozco si Lüdemann tiene conocimientos psicoanalíticos, pero esta explicación sobre Pablo parece una explicación del mecanismo de defensa formación reactiva, el cuál consiste en transformar una emoción o un impulso en su contrario; el odio sería amor, la enemistad a amistad, tolerancia en intolerancia, etc. Y esto sucede porque el sujeto tiene dificultades para manejarlas y se protege inconscientemente con este mecanismo de defensa. Pero esto lo pasaremos por alto, pues no pretendo hacer un análisis psicoanalítico.
Experiencias delirantes y alucinatorias
El Manual Diagnóstico y Estadístico de los Trastornos Mentales, clasifica a algunos trastornos que tienen como característica principal los delirios y las alucinaciones. Podemos encontrar algunos trastornos como el trastorno delirante, trastorno psicótico, esquizofreniforme, esquizofrénico, etc. También, tiene en cuenta características claves que definen los trastornos psicóticos como son, como se mencionó anteriormente, los delirios y alucinaciones.
Los delirios son creencias fijas que no son susceptibles de cambio a la luz de las pruebas en su contra. El contenido de los delirios puede incluir varios temas como persecuciones (es decir, la creencia de que uno va a ser perjudicado, acosado, perseguido, etc, por un individuo u organización), referenciales (es decir, la creencia de que ciertos gestos, comentarios, señales del medio ambiente, etc, se dirigen a uno mismo), de grandeza (es decir, cuando el sujeto cree que tiene habilidades ,riqueza o fama excepcionales), somáticos (es decir, preocupaciones referente a la salud y al funcionamiento de los órganos), etc.
Por otro lado, las alucinaciones son percepciones que tienen lugar sin la presencia de un estímulo externo. Son vívidas y claras, con toda la fuerza y el impacto de las percepciones normales, y no están sujetas al control voluntario. Pueden darse en cualquier modalidad sensorial, pero las alucinaciones auditivas habitualmente se experimentan en forma de voces, conocidas o desconocidas, que se perciben como diferentes del propio pensamiento. Las alucinaciones deben tener lugar en el contexto de un adecuado nivel de conciencia; aquellas que tienen lugar al quedarse uno dormido o al despertar se considera que está dentro del rango de las experiencias normales.
Algo que hay que destacar es que el mismo DSM-IV aclara que las alucinaciones pueden ser una parte normal de la experiencia religiosa en determinados contextos culturales.[4]
Tal parece que, hasta este punto, ya podemos descartar la teoría de las alucinaciones de Lüdemann, pues si hemos de valorar adecuadamente las alucinaciones de un individuo, pues la experiencia post-mortem de los discípulos era una experiencia normal y justificada, dado que es una experiencia religiosa, entendida en su tiempo y contexto. Sin mencionar, que no podemos diagnosticar como una “alucinación” a priori la experiencia de una persona sin, por lo menos, hacer una corta entrevista respecto a su experiencia, como se hace clínicamente. Pero este no será el caso, pues trataré de dar un argumento formal desde mi perspectiva como psicólogo.
La epistemología de las alucinaciones
Si analizamos correctamente los tipos de trastornos que son característicos por su naturaleza delirante y alucinatoria, nos daremos cuenta de que cada sujeto tiene experiencias totalmente distintas entre sí. Es decir, cuando un sujeto tiene una alucinación o un delirio, puede tener ciertas características en común para compartir con otros sujetos delirantes, sin embargo, su experiencia no es la misma pues cada sujeto la experimenta de forma diferente.
Por ejemplo, los sujetos que sufren de alucinaciones persecutorias tienen características experienciales en común como creer que alguien está conspirando en su contra, o que le engañan, lo espían o persiguen. Sin embargo, cada experiencia alucinatoria es epistémicamente distinta entre sí. Quizá un sujeto alucina con que lo están espiando un grupo de personas más allá de la realidad, sin cuerpo físico, mientras que otro sujeto piensa que es espiado por el gobierno o por su propia pareja.
Lo mismo sucede con las personas que tienen delirios, por ejemplo, somáticos. Los sujetos podrán tener características experienciales en común, como expresar una pérdida de control sobre la mente o el cuerpo, o que sus propios pensamientos han sido robados. Pero estas experiencias serán epistémicamente distintas entre sí, pues un sujeto puede experimentar la “pérdida de la mente” de una forma distinta a la de otro sujeto, o incluso podrían diferir entre causas como el “ladrón de sus pensamientos o mente”.
Podemos encontrar un caso clínico de trastorno delirante por consumo de cannabis, donde esta persona tiene antecedentes psiquiátricos durante los últimos dos años. El paciente se quejaba de dolor abdominal y en el pecho, según él, ocasionado por telequinesia, pues una vecina que era bruja se lo estaba provocando. Además de esto, colocaba por toda la casa diversos objetos para ahuyentar los malos espíritus.[5]
Por otro lado, tenemos el caso clínico de un hombre con trastorno delirante, donde afirmaba que, los policías y carabineros que vivían en su mismo edificio estaban perjudicándole sólo por simpatizar con una ideología diferente a ellos. Además, refiere que hablaban de él en la televisión y que el gas estaba envenenado, incluyendo el agua, por lo que tenía que comprar agua envasada y pedir comida por teléfono.[6]
Si analizamos correctamente estos dos casos, podemos ver que ambos sufren delirios de persecución, comparten características experienciales en común como ser conspirado por un tercero, y evitar ciertas actividades diarias por la creencia de que eran parte de la conspiración. Sin embargo, ambas experiencias son epistémicamente distintas entre sí, pues los “conspiradores” son distintos y no actúan de la misma manera, ni utilizan las mismas “formas” o “herramientas” para “conspirar” contra los pacientes mencionados.
La epistemología de la experiencia post-mortem de los discípulos
Ahora, vamos a aplicar el mismo análisis a las experiencias de los discípulos cuando vieron a Jesús nuevamente con vida. Pero antes, hay que anotar algo pues uno puede preguntar: ¿no es verdad que hay diferencias entre los relatos de la resurrección? Por ejemplo, Mateo y Marcos relatan que un ángel les habló a las mujeres, mientras que Lúcas y Juan dicen que había dos ángeles en la tumba.[7] ¿No es esta una experiencia epistémicamente distinta entre sujetos y, por lo tanto, sería un caso legítimo de alucinación o delirio?
Bueno, hay que aclarar que el caso de la experiencia respecto a los ángeles es algo secundario, pues la alucinación analizada en este escrito es la de la visión de Jesús por parte de sus discípulos. Por lo que sería irrelevante si fue o no una alucinación en todo el sentido de la palabra. Ahora, podemos rescatar un hecho importante sobre el caso de la resurrección y es que en múltiples ocasiones y bajo varias circunstancias, diferentes individuos y grupos de personas, experimentaron apariciones de Jesús vivo de entre los muertos.
Un caso experiencial que podemos encontrar en la biblia es el de Tomás, quien no estaba con los discípulos cuando había llegado Jesús, relatado en Juan 20:24-31. Tomás no creía lo que los discípulos le decían, habían visto a Jesús nuevamente. Sin embargo, Tomás objetaba que mientras no viera la marca de los clavos en sus manos y no sintiera su mano en su costado no creería. Luego de una semana, Jesús se apareció a los doce, y fue cuando le dijo a Tomás que tocara sus manos y su costado. Entonces él creyó.
Como podemos observar, la experiencia de Tomás fue totalmente distinta en primera persona (fue él quien tocó sus manos y su costado) a la de los demás discípulos. Sin embargo, esto no pudo haber sido una alucinación, ya que para que cumpla su naturaleza alucinógena, tendría que haber sido una persona distinta, en situaciones distintas, pues estaban todos reunidos y era Jesús mismo.
En otras palabras, la experiencia post-mortem no puede tratarse de una alucinación, pues se observó a la misma persona (Jesús), en la misma situación (los discípulos reunidos) e incluso las mismas palabras escuchadas (“la paz sea con ustedes”, “porque me has visto, has creído…”).
El argumento
Luego del análisis mencionado anteriormente y habiendo explicado que las alucinaciones son epistémicamente distintas entre sí, aunque existan características en común, y que las experiencias de los discípulos, recalcando la de Tomás, son la misma, podríamos formalizar un argumento de la siguiente manera.
1.- Si las experiencias alucinatorias son epistémicamente distintas entre sujetos, entonces los apóstoles no pudieron haber tenido la misma experiencia alucinatoria.
2.- Los apóstoles tuvieron la misma experiencia post-mortem, pues se trata de la misma persona (Jesús) y la misma circunstancia (discípulos reunidos).
3.- Por lo tanto, los apóstoles no pudieron haber tenido una alucinación.
4.- Por lo tanto, la teoría de las alucinaciones es falsa.
Pero ¿no es verdad que también se apareció a otras personas quienes estaban en situaciones y circunstancias distintas? En efecto, incluso la experiencia pudo haber sido muy distinta a la de los apóstoles. Sin embargo, aún sigue tratándose de la misma persona y la misma creencia de haber resucitado luego de haber sido ejecutado por la corte Romana.
Ahora bien, cabe mencionar que las experiencias alucinógenas no son sólo experiencias epistémicamente distintas entre sujetos, sino que también son privadas. Es decir, cada alucinación es vivida enteramente en y sólo en primera persona, nunca son experimentadas en grupo. ¿Esto quiere decir que las alucinaciones grupales no existen? Efectivamente, las experiencias grupales no existen, si por grupal se entiende como un conjunto de X cantidad de personas, experimentando exactamente lo mismo, al mismo tiempo o que incluso tengan el mismo desorden psicótico, o que hayan ingerido la misma sustancia en la misma cantidad. De otra forma no puede ser considerado una “alucinación grupal”. Esto es ridículamente improbable.
Así que, siguiendo con el argumento anterior, podríamos reformularlo de la siguiente manera:
1.- Si las experiencias alucinatorias son epistémicamente distintas entre sí y son experiencias privadas, entonces los apóstoles no pudieron haber tenido la misma experiencia post-mortem de Jesús.
2.- Los apóstoles sí tuvieron la misma experiencia post-mortem de la misma persona de Jesús.
3.- Por lo tanto, las experiencias de los apóstoles no son epistémicamente distintas entre sí ni fueron experiencias privadas. Por lo que no se consideran alucinaciones.
4.- Por lo tanto, los apóstoles no tuvieron una alucinación.
5.- Por lo tanto, la teoría de las alucinaciones es falsa.
Conclusión
Es muy probable que este argumento no sea lo suficientemente lógico y que haga agua por muchos lados, pues está claro que se requiere explicar muchas cosas de naturaleza psicológicas como delirios extravagantes, comorbilidad entre trastornos, etc. Pero la intención desde un inicio fue no extenderse en explicar cada término en profundidad.
Quizá este argumento no sea el definitivo contra toda objeción de naturaleza psicológica por parte de ateos, ya que siempre encontraremos objeciones como “los cristianos son esquizofrénicos porque escuchan la voz de Dios” o simplemente nos seguirán llamando neuróticos. Pero, cualquier psicólogo serio sabe que para poder diagnosticar a una persona con algún trastorno o poder concluir clínicamente que una persona tuvo una alucinación genuina, se necesitan estudios y entrevistas en condiciones. Pero esto es entendible, pues estamos acostumbrados a usar estos términos para cualquier situación fuera de lo normal; “estás alucinando”, “puros delirios tuyos”.
De igual manera, abro la invitación a colegas para que sigan el trabajo establecido en este escrito para reforzarlo o para formular otro argumento de naturaleza psicológica para su uso en la apologética actual y futura ya que, desafortunadamente, la psicología es atacada constantemente por ciertos círculos cristianos y casi no tiene presencia dentro de la apologética. Pero ese tema será tratado en otra ocasión.
Referencias:
[1] Lane Craig, William, Visiones de Jesús: una evaluación crítica de la hipótesis de alucinación de Gerd Lüdemann. Disponible en https://www.reasonablefaith.org/writings/scholarly-writings/historical-jesus/visions-of-jesus-a-critical-assessment-of-gerd-ludemanns-hallucination-hypo/
[2] Ídem.
[3] Ídem.
[4] APA, Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5ta, ed) Pp.87
[5] Gúrpide, Caso clínico; trastorno delirante en consumidor de cannabis, disponible en: http://www.madrid.org/cs/Satellite?blobcol=urldata&blobheader=application%2Fpdf&blobheadername1=Content-disposition&blobheadername2=cadena&blobheadervalue1=filename%3Dcaso9-+CANNABIS+CASOS+CLINICOS-18.pdf&blobheadervalue2=language%3Des%26site%3DPortalSalud&blobkey=id&blobable=MungoBlobs&blobwhere=1202790953505&ssbinary=true
[6] Diaz, Mancilla, Ortíz & Osorio, Caso clínico de trastorno delirante, disponible en: http://docs.bvsalud.org/biblioref/2018/12/967562/208-216.pdf
[7] Hernández de Alba, Claudia, Las contradicciones en el relato de la resurrección, disponible en: https://hoy.com.do/las-contradicciones-en-el-relato-de-resurreccion/
Kike Medina, radica en México, licenciado en psicología, se dedica al estudio de la apologética. Co-fundador del proyecto “Apologeeks” y es parte del equipo de Filósofo Cristiano.